07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE EMBODIED M<strong>IN</strong>D<br />

seem to have attracted Kant’s attention early on, the influence of Hume,<br />

Crusius and others may have sharpened his awareness of the limits of<br />

human knowledge and made him adopt the idea of the primacy of<br />

experiential knowledge. The influence of Crusius is emphasized by,<br />

among others, Tonelli, 78 pointing to the fact that Crusius, distancing<br />

himself from Leibniz, maintained that the domain of human knowledge<br />

was more limited than the rationalists had assumed. Even if Kant never<br />

became an orthodox follower of Crusius, Tonelli argues, his early<br />

philosophy was clearly influenced by him. I also think that even if Hume<br />

did not influence Kant as much as is often supposed, he may nevertheless<br />

also have contributed to the empiricism of 1766. 79<br />

Looking forward, Dreams of a spirit-seer is sometimes heralded as a<br />

sign of a new critical outlook which will find its full expression in the<br />

Critique. For instance, Nierhaus argues that at this time Kant was<br />

already concerned with what was later to form the centre of his critical<br />

project, establishing the limits of human knowledge through a critical<br />

examination of our cognitive capacities. 80 I think this is largely true. Of<br />

course, as Shell points out, this does not mean that in Dreams of a spiritseer<br />

Kant presents anything like the full scale critical theory found in the<br />

Critique. 81 However, like Nierhaus, Shell sees in the boundary-setting<br />

activity of Dreams of a spirit-seer an anticipation of Kant’s more<br />

developed critical stance. I also think there are other ways in which<br />

Dreams of a spirit-seer points forward to the Critique, as will become<br />

apparent later.<br />

Before that it may be worth noting that Kant’s criticism of ontology<br />

in Dreams of a spirit-seer also has a moral and pragmatic dimension.<br />

Ontology should be avoided because it is a waste of time, taking energy<br />

away from more useful occupations. Neither does it seem to have any<br />

positive effect on public morality, Kant argues. Even people who are<br />

convinced that there is an afterlife, as ontology claims there is, continue<br />

to do wrong. Consequently, rather than waste our time on ontology, we<br />

should focus our energies on doing things that may improve our lives on<br />

earth. This point is dramatically expressed in the last lines of the text:<br />

borrowing words from Voltaire’s Candide, Kant advises the reader to<br />

leave all ontological speculations behind and seek his happiness working<br />

in the garden:<br />

78<br />

Tonelli (1969).<br />

79<br />

Cf. e.g. Borowski’s testimony in Gross (1993), 69.<br />

80<br />

Nierhaus (1962), 116.<br />

81<br />

Shell (1996), 127ff.<br />

43

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!