07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SPATIAL SCHEMATISM 193<br />

account the spatial form of this object, i.e. its shape, and this is done, by<br />

means of an act similar to an act of construction. Now, how does this<br />

help us towards a better understanding of the relation between<br />

subsumption and construction in Kant’s theory of schematism? As the<br />

theory needed to answer this question is only hinted at in the schematism<br />

chapter, we have to try to deduce it from the little that is said. Let us try<br />

to do so, however, and in order not to stray too far, let us concentrate on<br />

the triangle example.<br />

Following the example of the triangle, Kant tells us that his theory of<br />

schematism may be used to solve the old problem of the generality of<br />

concepts, namely how can a concept be general and still apply to<br />

particulars which, moreover, are not congruent? If we think of the<br />

concept as an image, or something like an image, the required generality<br />

would never be attained, he argues.<br />

No image of a triangle would ever be adequate to the concept of it.<br />

For it would not attain the generality of the concept, which makes<br />

this valid for all triangles, right or acute, etc., but would always be<br />

limited to one part of this sphere. (A 141/B 180)<br />

If we instead think of the concept of a triangle as a rule-governing<br />

practice through which all existing triangles may be produced, the<br />

problem of generality is solved. Let us represent the rule of this practice<br />

linguistically like this: ‘Draw three straight lines in a plane. Each line<br />

must intersect the other two. The triangle is the figure constituted by the<br />

lines connecting the intersections.’ By means of this practice, an infinite<br />

set of triangles may be produced. Further, since the rule is unspecific<br />

regarding angles and distances, each new triangle produced is potentially<br />

different from the others. However, as long as they are produced<br />

according to the rule, they are all triangles. The problem of generality is<br />

solved because the generality is guaranteed by the procedure. In a sense,<br />

the generality is found in the procedure rather than in each individual<br />

triangle.<br />

Kant has now demonstrated that the procedure for producing a<br />

triangle may be conceived of as general in the same sense that a concept<br />

is usually considered to be general. However, the main question is still<br />

left unanswered, which is how does this help us understand what<br />

subsumption has to do with construction? Let us assume that we have a<br />

triangle before us, a triangle empirically given, for example one drawn on<br />

a piece of paper or made of wood. How do we recognize this triangle as a<br />

triangle? And how does this recognition involve an act of construction?<br />

What does Kant mean when he suggests that the capacity to recognize it

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!