07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>KANT</strong>’S TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY<br />

247<br />

cognitive capacities and powers available to us. And, as we have seen, the<br />

Critique actually offers such a theory. However, the above questions also<br />

have an epistemic aspect, and Kant never fails to emphasize that this is<br />

his most basic concern in the Critique. When we ask how it is possible for<br />

us to attain objective knowledge of the world, there is introduced a<br />

concept of objectivity according to which a statement about the world<br />

can be either true or false. Thus, the question of objectivity goes beyond<br />

asking merely how our knowledge is produced. It concerns the validity of<br />

our knowledge claims.<br />

How is it possible for us to attain objective knowledge of the world<br />

given that the origin of this knowledge is subjective in the sense specified?<br />

Kant’s answer is that such knowledge may be proved to be possible when<br />

we realize that some of the subjective elements on which our knowledge<br />

is based are actually that which makes experience (or knowledge)<br />

possible. They are what Kant calls ‘a priori conditions of experience’. In<br />

order to make this theoretical move to solve the problem, however, we<br />

also have to show that these a priori conditions make possible what Kant<br />

calls ‘synthetic a priori knowledge’ of the world. This synthetic a priori<br />

knowledge is knowledge of the necessary order in which the world<br />

appears to us, or the determinations that the world needs to have in<br />

order to appear as more than a mere manifold, to use a well known<br />

Kantian expression. That objects exist beside each other in Euclidean<br />

space is an example of what Kant here means by order. Causality, the<br />

fact that in the empirical world every event has a cause, is another<br />

example. Kant’s point is that the world appears to us as ordered and<br />

determined because our a priori forms of experience, even if they are all<br />

subjective, are conditions of synthetic a priori knowledge of the kind just<br />

suggested. This is why Kant can phrase what he claims to be the main<br />

question of the Critique as ‘How is synthetic a priori knowledge<br />

possible?’<br />

This question is also implied by Kant’s general definition of<br />

transcendental philosophy, which has already been discussed, as ‘a<br />

system of transcendental knowledge (Erkenntnis) which deals with the<br />

specific manner in which we achieve knowledge of objects (Erkenntnisart<br />

von Gegenständen) as far as this is possible a priori’ (A 11/B 25). An<br />

essential mark of this transcendental philosophy, Kant points out, is that<br />

all its concepts are pure a priori: They contain nothing empirical (A 14/B<br />

28). Later the same point is stated like this:<br />

I call all representations pure (in the transcendental sense) in which<br />

nothing is to be encountered that belongs to sensation. (A 20/B 34)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!