07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

214<br />

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> THE TRANSCENDENTAL<br />

philosophy to refer to phenomena known from the empirical world.<br />

When, for instance, in his transcendental philosophy Kant talks about<br />

the affection of the cognitive agent, this cannot be interpreted as a theory<br />

of physical affection. Neither can Kant’s transcendental theory of<br />

cognitive activity be interpreted as referring to embodied acts. To do this<br />

would involve what may be termed a ‘transcendental transgression’ and<br />

would mean that we gave up the distinction between the transcendental<br />

and empirical that Kant demands we uphold.<br />

A version of this position is represented by Strawson. According to<br />

Strawson, Kant tries to discover the limits of human knowledge from a<br />

position outside these limits, or, as Strawson puts it, Kant ‘seeks to draw<br />

the bounds of sense from a point outside them’. 2 From this he concludes<br />

that the syntheses described in the Critique belong to a theory of a mind<br />

that cannot be empirically observed. Kant’s theory of these syntheses,<br />

therefore, cannot be interpreted as referring to anything we know from<br />

the empirical world. A similar point is made by Bennett. 3 As we have<br />

seen, not all agree with Strawson and Bennett on these points. So for<br />

instance, Falkenstein argues that Kant’s critical theory of space in the<br />

Transcendental aesthetic implies that the mind of the Critique is<br />

embodied, and, consequently that parts of the cognitive process<br />

described in Kant’s transcendental psychology also involve the body. 4<br />

Starting out from Kant’s theory of schematism, Shaper argues it implies<br />

that the mind described in the Critique has to be conceived of as existing<br />

in time and so not fully outside the spatio-temporal domain. 5 Even if I<br />

agree with both Falkenstein, Shaper and others on the point that the<br />

mind described in the Critique both can and must be conceived of as<br />

embodied, I also take the position defended by Strawson, Bennett and<br />

others seriously. I think that Kant’s way of presenting his transcendental<br />

philosophy may very easily be misread in a way that may seem to make<br />

such a position unavoidable.<br />

In promoting his transcendental idealism, Kant argues that all our<br />

experience is representational and that time and space are nothing but<br />

subjective forms of intuition. Moreover, he claims that there is an aspect<br />

of reality (the world as it is independently of our way of experiencing it)<br />

2<br />

Strawson (1973), 12.<br />

3<br />

Discussing Kant’s theory of sensibility, Bennett argues that what Kant in the<br />

Critique calls the outer sense cannot be identified with our biological senseorgans<br />

(Bennett (1966), 18).<br />

4<br />

Falkenstein (1995).<br />

5<br />

Shaper (1992).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!