07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CAUSALITY <strong>AND</strong> COMMON SENSE PHYSICS 299<br />

it is in its interest to move. If not, it remains at rest. However, interaction<br />

still takes place. This point is perhaps best described by saying that the<br />

child’s knowledge of causality is embedded in its general propensity to<br />

move or to remain in rest relative to other objects so that desired<br />

consequences are produced, and unwanted are avoided. As before,<br />

‘knowledge’ means here sensorimotor knowledge, signifying that the<br />

child at this age has no knowledge of causality independently of the<br />

practice.<br />

In a previous chapter I argued that if there is a level at which the<br />

relational categories exist as embodied practices, then these have to be<br />

practices entertained at every awake moment of our lives. I have now<br />

identified what I have called a practice of causality that satisfies this<br />

condition. I have also argued, following suggestions made by Piaget, that<br />

this practice may be conceived of as an a priori condition of experience.<br />

So this practice seems to have a function similar to the one ascribed to<br />

the category of causality in Kant’s transcendental theory. If we accept<br />

that there is a level at which the category of causality exists as an<br />

embodied practice, the practice just defined may well be the practice we<br />

are looking for. Note, as before, that I do not take this idea to be<br />

explicitly promoted in the Critique. My claim is only that it is Kantian in<br />

the weaker sense that is compatible with basic ideas underlying a number<br />

of Kantian texts, including some parts of the Critique.<br />

Note, finally, that just as the relational categories work together<br />

according to Kant’s theory in the Critique, there is a sense in which the<br />

two practices now identified, those of object-permanence and causality,<br />

presuppose each other in a sense that makes them hard to distinguish in<br />

an actual situation. To take into account the causality of the world means<br />

to take into account that objects exist and that they have a permanence<br />

beyond our perception of them. Therefore there is a level at which these<br />

two practices converge into a general practice of interaction, i.e. they are<br />

at play in every interaction we have with the objects of our world.<br />

11.5 Sensorimotor intelligence in the adult<br />

It may be that this argument is reasonable as long as we talk about<br />

children in the sensorimotor period, but what about adults? The<br />

cognitive capacities of the adult are dramatically more sophisticated than<br />

those of the young child. Where the adult is concerned, would it not be<br />

natural to see the categories as functions present within these more<br />

sophisticated cognitive faculties? I think not, and my argument for this is<br />

based in part on an aspect of Piaget’s cognitive theory that has so far not<br />

been mentioned. It is the idea that sensorimotor intelligence is present

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!