07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

RATIONALITY <strong>AND</strong> EMBODIED <strong>PRACTICE</strong><br />

or tacit standards or rules. Moreover, if we examine these standards or<br />

rules, they typically relate to the achievement of an end. Walking is a<br />

practice, according to this, as walking is typically done for a purpose (in a<br />

minimal sense the purpose is to move from one place to another) and as<br />

there are tacit rules or standards by which we may evaluate the quality of<br />

the walking taking place. When we do not generally make these rules<br />

explicit, it may be because we (or most of us) are skilled walkers for whom<br />

these rules are tacitly understood. This does not exclude the fact that we<br />

may sometimes make them explicit, for instance when comparing and<br />

evaluating the walking of two children who are learning to walk for the<br />

first time.<br />

Let me now specify what I mean by an ‘embodied practice’. In using<br />

this expression I do not mean to imply that the participants of an<br />

embodied practice participate only with their bodies. They participate<br />

with the whole of themselves, body and mind. It is the fact that both are<br />

involved that gives the practice status as embodied. The examples given<br />

by MacIntyre are all examples of what I shall call embodied practices. So<br />

are Kant’s examples, which will be further considered below. In some<br />

cases, an embodied practice may also involve various instruments. The<br />

doctor, for instance, in his medical practice, which, according to my<br />

definition is embodied, uses a number of instruments.<br />

It may be objected that all practices are embodied, and thus, that the<br />

term ‘embodied practice’ is a pleonasm. The response to such a criticism<br />

may depend on the philosophical outlook of the respondent. One might,<br />

for instance, claim that there are acts that are purely mental, and that<br />

such acts may be performed according to a set of rules in order to attain<br />

some end. Following our definition, these acts would then count as a<br />

practice. According to some interpretations of Kant, this is how his<br />

theory of the human employment of the categories is to be understood.<br />

The categories are then conceived as rules directing our mental<br />

operations so that objective knowledge is produced. According to this<br />

model, and our definition of practice, our employment of the categories<br />

is then a practice taking place solely at the mental level. Other such<br />

practices may also be imagined. The term ‘embodied practice’ signals<br />

that such practices, if we accept that they exist, are not to be included<br />

within the extension of the term.<br />

3.2 Pragmatism<br />

In contemporary philosophy the term ‘pragmatism’ is often associated<br />

with what was around the beginning of the twentieth century the most<br />

85

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!