07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

40<br />

to communicate, his theory seems to be not that the mind is an<br />

independent monad but rather that a human being must be thought of as<br />

a single substance of which mind and body are nothing but different<br />

aspects or dimensions. It is not obvious that this theory is affected by the<br />

problems that, for instance, Laywine claims Kant was facing.<br />

According to Schönfeld, Kant also struggled with the problem of<br />

combining on the one hand the idea that the mind was part of the<br />

physical universe and on the other the idea that it was immortal. Kant<br />

was committed to the idea that the mind or the soul continued to exist<br />

after it left its mortal body, Schönfeld maintains, and he wanted his<br />

general theory of the world to have room in it for this idea of<br />

immortality. I think there is little reason to doubt that Kant believed in<br />

the afterlife of the soul. However, I do not see it as obvious that he<br />

perceived this idea as a problem in need of a philosophical solution. If he<br />

did, he would surely have raised it and discussed it more explicitly.<br />

However, the immortality of the soul almost never surfaces in Kant’s<br />

explicit discourse, and when it does, for instance in Universal natural<br />

history, it is combined with an explicit agnosticism. Despite what our<br />

senses and consciousness tell us, Kant argues, we do not really know what<br />

a human being is, and we know even less about the afterlife. 75 It may also<br />

be worth noting that he does not seem to find this agnosticism<br />

problematic. On the contrary, he seems to be entirely happy to move the<br />

question of the immortality of the soul out of the realm of philosophical<br />

discourse and into the field of belief. In his critical phase, the idea that<br />

the soul is immortal was explicitly classified as an ‘idea of faith’. Kant’s<br />

explicit agnosticism in Universal natural history may be read as a sign<br />

that this perspective may have been present as early as 1755. If so, the<br />

idea of immortality would hardly have had the force to provoke a<br />

philosophical crisis.<br />

Finally, if Dreams of a spirit-seer is the product of a crisis following<br />

Kant’s previous ontological commitments, one would have expected him<br />

to now abstain from any further excursions into this dubious field of<br />

human enquiry. However, as we have seen, in Dreams of a spirit-seer<br />

Kant does not reject ontology in an absolute sense. The idea that the<br />

mind is present in the body qua activity does not have to be regarded as<br />

an ontological thesis. However, by claiming that this idea is compatible<br />

with the idea that the mind as such is single and without extension, he is<br />

obviously thinking against the background of classical ontology. He even<br />

seems to adopt the above-mentioned idea as his own position within this<br />

75 Ak I: 366.<br />

THE EMBODIED M<strong>IN</strong>D

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!