07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

80<br />

RATIONALITY <strong>AND</strong> EMBODIED <strong>PRACTICE</strong><br />

analyzed at the level of the behavior of this agent. The new theory of<br />

rationality resulting from this change in perspective is found in texts such<br />

as On the common saying from 1793, Anthropology from 1798, Logic<br />

from 1800 and On pedagogy from 1803. I will refer to these texts as<br />

Kant’s writings on anthropology, pedagogy and logic. This way of<br />

referring to them is also meant to indicate that each text covers more<br />

than its title suggests and that they overlap thematically. For instance, he<br />

approaches pedagogical topics not only in On pedagogy, but also in<br />

Anthropology, and his published writings on both pedagogy and logic<br />

include passages relevant to our understanding of his anthropology.<br />

In Kant’s writings on anthropology, pedagogy and logic, human<br />

rationality is discussed with reference to human acts and behavior, or<br />

more specifically, to the human capacity for handling rules and to act<br />

according to rules. Acts that take place according to rules, or sets of rules,<br />

he calls ‘practice’. So if we are going to give a rough initial<br />

characterization of Kant’s new theoretical outlook, we may say that it<br />

associates the concept of rationality with that of practice. In the above<br />

mentioned texts he gives a number of examples of practices associated<br />

with rationality. In all of these practices, the human agent is evidently an<br />

embodied agent, and the practices may consequently be qualified as<br />

embodied practices. So we can also say that Kant now promotes the idea<br />

of an association between the concepts of embodied practice and human<br />

rationality. Embodied practices, moreover, are not seen merely as<br />

expressions of underlying rational processes taking place, for instance, in<br />

the brain or on a mental level. They are seen as the medium in which<br />

human beings realize themselves in a very basic sense as rational beings.<br />

The term ‘rationality’ is here used in a broad sense and includes all the<br />

skills and capacities through which man appears as a rational animal in<br />

the Aristotelian sense of the term. I will say more about this later.<br />

Kant takes a practice to be a set of acts having a goal. When we<br />

participate in a practice, we do it for a purpose, because we want to<br />

achieve something. This means there is also a pragmatic aspect to Kant’s<br />

definition of a practice. This pragmatic aspect is also transferred to his<br />

theory of rationality, or so I shall argue. I will refer to this theory as<br />

Kant’s ‘pragmatic theory of embodied rationality’. I do not claim that<br />

this pragmatic theory of embodied rationality exhausts all Kant has to<br />

say about human rationality but I think that it occupies a central position<br />

within his general theory of rationality. I shall return to this in due<br />

course.<br />

Exactly when Kant’s pragmatic theory of embodied rationality<br />

emerged is hard to say. Even if the above-mentioned texts were<br />

published towards the end of his life, they are based for the most part on

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!