07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE RELATIONAL CATEGORIES 283<br />

the category of causality. This category, then, is proven to be an a priori<br />

condition of what was taken to be evident, and the proof is concluded. In<br />

giving his proof of the transcendental function of causality, Kant does not<br />

require us to constantly investigate the exact causal relations of the<br />

elements of our environment in order to objectively determine time, at<br />

least not in the way I read him. I take Kant’s point to be that the fact that<br />

we experience the world as a series of events taking place in an<br />

irreversible time order confirms that we already apply the category of<br />

causality in our experience, even if we are not explicitly aware of this.<br />

This is possible, because, as we have seen, Kant contends that a<br />

significant part of our cognitive process may take place at an obscure<br />

level of consciousness.<br />

10.3 The third analogy<br />

In my presentation of the two previous analogies, I have tried to<br />

emphasis their main structure, deliberately omitting a number of details.<br />

My discussion of the third analogy will be even briefer. In short, Kant<br />

claims that determining two objects as simultaneous require the category<br />

of reciprocal causal interaction. He has previously stated that time has<br />

only two modi, that is, succession and simultaneity (B 226/A182). In the<br />

second analogy he argued that objective succession presupposes causality.<br />

Thus, the first of the two modi of time was taken care of. The second<br />

modus, simultaneity, is the topic of the third analogy. As I understand it,<br />

Kant’s theory of the category of reciprocal causal interaction is little<br />

more than an extension of his theory of the category of causality.<br />

According to this theory, while the latter determines a causal relation to<br />

be present between A and B, the former determines that it also, at the<br />

same time, is present between B and A. If this is right, it follows that<br />

causality, alongside substantiality, is the essential principle of time<br />

determination. It also follows that simultaneity is a special case of<br />

succession. When A and B causally influence each other reciprocally, we<br />

may say both that A succeeds B and that B succeeds A, which can be true<br />

only if they are simultaneous and the time between A and B is zero. 6<br />

6 This comes close to the cases described in the second analogy at A 203ff/ B<br />

247ff. Here Kant discusses cases in which cause and effect exist simultaneously.<br />

Actually some of these cases, such as the iron ball resting on a pillow, might have<br />

been used as examples of reciprocal interaction just as well as unidirectional<br />

causality. In this case, there is causal directionality present both from the ball to<br />

the pillow and from the pillow to the ball.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!