07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

252<br />

<strong>KANT</strong>’S TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY<br />

practice that does have such a function, that is, a practice that is a<br />

condition for having experience. The term ‘experience’ is used here, as<br />

before, in its strong Kantian sense, which means, among other things<br />

that it is an experience of objects that are determined. The following<br />

example focuses on one such determination, size.<br />

Imagine we are to measure the size of an object, for instance a table. 14<br />

In order to do so, we need an object to use as a measuring rod. The<br />

measuring is performed by placing the rod next to the table. If the table<br />

is larger than the rod, we will have to successively move the rod from one<br />

position to another along the object, while memorizing in the mind, or<br />

perhaps by counting on the fingers, how many times this takes place. In<br />

doing this, our acts are not arbitrary but take place in a regular way.<br />

They also have a goal, finding the size of the table. According to the<br />

definition of a practice given above, they may be regarded as a practice.<br />

Let us call it ‘the practice of finding the size of an object’.<br />

As can be seen, we would not attain knowledge about the size of the<br />

table without this practice. Or to use a more Kantian expression, we<br />

would not be able to determine this particular aspect of the table without<br />

it. Where this particular aspect of our experience of the table is<br />

concerned, we may say that the practice is an a priori condition of having<br />

it.<br />

8.5 An empirical or a transcendental deduction?<br />

There is one problem with the example just offered which has to do with<br />

Kant’s distinction between an empirical and a transcendental deduction.<br />

It seems we have only given an empirical account of how the table is<br />

measured, so what we have done, at best, is provide what Kant calls an<br />

empirical deduction, telling the story of how the concept of the size of the<br />

table originates in our practice.<br />

First, let us notice, that even if Kant seems to be drawing a sharp<br />

distinction between the two sorts of deductions in the Critique, the first<br />

having to do merely with origin, the other with validity, it is not evident<br />

that in his transcendental epistemology he only operates on one side of<br />

this distinction. Both in the A- and the B-deduction of the categories and<br />

elsewhere in the Critique, Kant frequently refers to the origin of our<br />

knowledge. He also seems to think that, in doing this he is saying<br />

something about the justification of this knowledge (cf. e.g. A 66/B 90<br />

and A 86/B 119). There is more than one way to respond to this. We<br />

14<br />

I owe this example, and also its interpretation, to Saugstad (1992), 388.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!