07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> THE TRANSCENDENTAL 239<br />

representational does not jeopardize their epistemic status. Quite the<br />

opposite, it frees them from the doubt directed at them by skeptical<br />

idealism, and so transcendental idealism necessary leads to what Kant<br />

calls empirical realism.<br />

At first sight Kant’s story here seems to be rather different from the<br />

one I have told above. Nothing is said about an embodied mind. Instead,<br />

he seems to be giving us an account of a mind almost indistinguishable<br />

from the mind as it is according to Hume and Descartes, a disembodied<br />

mind aware only of its own inner states. This mind, Kant emphasizes, is<br />

the only thing of which we have immediate and secure knowledge.<br />

Moreover, what we take to be objects existing independently in space<br />

are, transcendentally considered, nothing but representations in this<br />

mind. However, we also know that Kant vigorously resisted the idealism<br />

of Descartes and Hume. Consequently, whatever the message of the<br />

above argument is, it should not be confused with the position of these<br />

philosophers.<br />

Kant may himself have become aware that this way of stating his<br />

point might lead readers to confuse his transcendental idealism with the<br />

more dubious forms of idealism of Descartes and Hume. No wonder,<br />

then, that he rewrote the paralogism chapter for the B-edition and also<br />

added a newly written Refutation of idealism. However, the fact that he<br />

rewrote the A-version of the paralogism chapter does not mean that he<br />

took its argument to be false. More probably he feared that it would be<br />

misread, or that more was needed to get his point across than what was<br />

said in the A-edition. Actually, in the Refutation of idealism of the Bedition,<br />

Kant repeats what we have just seen him claim in the A-edition<br />

version of the paralogism chapter. He discusses a position called<br />

problematical idealism which is an idealism of a Cartesian sort, in which<br />

the existence of external objects is not denied, but claimed to be dubious.<br />

This idealism is based on the assumption that we have no immediate<br />

experience [unmittelbahre Erfahrung] outside ourselves. This is a<br />

reasonable and well founded philosophical claim, he maintains (B 275). 23<br />

But does not this make Kant a Cartesian? Does not this make his<br />

position just what he wants to avoid? In the B-edition he still attacks<br />

Cartesian idealism, so in what way is his position different? One way of<br />

seeing it as different and giving sense to the argument found both in the<br />

23<br />

However, he now also adds another argument to prove the existence of<br />

external objects. Our experience of time, which belongs to the inner sense, and<br />

thus to the domain which even the sceptic accepts as certain, is possible only if<br />

outer objects exist. This argument will be further explored in a later chapter.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!