07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

156<br />

SPATIAL EXPERIENCE <strong>AND</strong> THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE<br />

reference to the body and to embodied acts and practices. For instance,<br />

we have seen him argue that our capacity to grasp an object is a<br />

condition of our capacity to form a concept of its shape. In this passage<br />

emphasis is placed on acts involving the whole body, such as running,<br />

throwing, trying to hit a target, etc. In an earlier chapter, I called the<br />

ideas underlying this way of thinking Kant’s ‘theory of the embodied<br />

constitution of spatial representations’, or his ‘embodied theory of space’<br />

for short.<br />

In this and the following chapter I will argue that the theory of space<br />

and spatial experience as it is found in the Critique, or Kant’s ‘critical<br />

theory of space’, for short, is remarkably similar in structure to his<br />

embodied theory of space. It is true that in his critical theory there are no<br />

explicit references made to the body, at least, not in the way we see them<br />

in Directions in space, Orientation, Anthropology and On pedagogy. At<br />

the centre of the critical theory of space stands the abstract notion of a<br />

mind [Gemüt], the relation of which to the body is not specified, and the<br />

abstract notion of space, defined as the a priori form of intuition. This<br />

form is claimed to have its source a priori in the mind. To be more<br />

specific, it is said to have its origin in the activity of the mind, or so I shall<br />

argue. At no point, however, is this activity said to be embodied in the<br />

way we have seen in the texts examined above. The absence of explicit<br />

references to the body is especially noticeable in the Transcendental<br />

aesthetic, the part of the Critique dedicated to Kant’s critical<br />

examination of sensibility, which is also the part where space is first<br />

discussed in the Critique. Despite this absence, I will maintain that his<br />

critical theory of space is remarkably similar in structure to his embodied<br />

theory of space. Based on this similarity, and based also on other<br />

theoretical reflections, I shall put forward the thesis that the former<br />

theory may be read, in part, as an abstract version of the latter. The task<br />

of this and the following chapter is to provide evidence for this claim.<br />

The reason why Kant’s critical discussion of space is allowed to<br />

occupy two whole chapters should come as no surprise. Alongside time,<br />

space is one of the main topics of the Critique, and he returns to discuss it<br />

from various angles throughout the text. I also hope that by discussing his<br />

critical theory of space at some length the foundations will be established<br />

to support my interpretation of other parts of the Critique, namely his<br />

critical theory of time and the categories.<br />

By claiming that Kant’s critical theory of space is, in part, an abstract<br />

version of his embodied theory of space, I mean that the abstract<br />

character of the former is, in part, due to the fact that explicit references<br />

to the body have been removed from the latter. More specifically, I claim<br />

that the abstract notion of the mind, found in the Critique should be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!