07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

251<br />

means that ‘a priori’ may be used in a correspondingly narrow sense to<br />

denote that in a representation that does not originate in the affection of<br />

the mind, but in the activity of the cognitive agent. This conforms to the<br />

final of the three points stated above, something is a priori when it<br />

originates in the activity of the agent. In what follows I shall take this to<br />

be an essential defining mark of the Kantian a priori. 11<br />

The claim just made will be of significance in the further discussion in<br />

more than one way. First, I shall use it in support of the idea that the<br />

categories may be conceived of as embodied practices after all. The logic<br />

of my argument is this. If we accept that a defining mark of the a priori is<br />

that it originates in the activity of the agent, then an embodied practice is<br />

a priori in this specific sense. An embodied practice is an activity<br />

performed by an agent, thus, we may also say that it originates in the<br />

agent. 12 This alone, of course, does not prove that the categories are<br />

embodied practices, or that we may legitimately conceive of them as<br />

such. In order to make this probable, we also have to show that there are<br />

practices satisfying the first and second demands listed above. We must<br />

demonstrate that there are embodied practices that are conditions for<br />

having experience, and that produce knowledge that is necessarily true<br />

and universal. This I shall do next.<br />

8.4 Embodied practice as a condition of experience<br />

In this section I shall argue that there are embodied practices that are<br />

conditions for having experience in a Kantian sense, and that produce<br />

knowledge that is necessarily true and universal. That there are<br />

embodied practices with such a function may perhaps not strike the<br />

reader as evident. 13<br />

Let me therefore give an example of an embodied<br />

11<br />

<strong>KANT</strong>’S TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY<br />

The a priori may of course also be defined in opposition to the empirical<br />

relative to the first and second of the marks listed above defining the a priori. The<br />

point is then that 1) while the a priori is a condition of having (empirical)<br />

experience, (empirical) experience is conditioned by the a priori, and 2) while the<br />

a priori produces knowledge which is necessarily true and universal, the empirical<br />

cannot do this: empirical claims are merely contingent ( cf. e.g. A 91/B 123 and<br />

A 196/B 214).<br />

12<br />

This is only meant as a brief suggestion here. I will say more about it below in<br />

discussing the normativity of a practice.<br />

13<br />

Within the Wittgensteinian tradition, however, there is a growing awareness<br />

that embodied practices may be conditions for having experience in a Kantian or<br />

quasi-Kantian sense. Cf. e.g. Lear (1986) and Railton (2000). I will return to this<br />

point below.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!