07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SPATIAL EXPERIENCE <strong>AND</strong> THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE 161<br />

At the beginning of the Transcendental aesthetic, ‘sensibility’ is<br />

defined as the capacity to be affected.<br />

The capacity (receptivity) to acquire representations through the way<br />

in which we are affected by objects is called sensibility. (A 19/B 33) 8<br />

At A 19/B 33 sensibility is also defined as the origin of our intuitions<br />

[Anschauungen]. All intuitions have two aspects, Kant further explains,<br />

one is the immediate effect of an object affecting the mind and is called<br />

sensation [Empfindung] (A 19-20/B 34). The other is what he refers to as<br />

the pure form of intuition. This term refers to the Kantian idea that the<br />

empirical content of cognition is intuited in certain temporal and spatial<br />

relations, which are claimed to exist a priori in the mind (A 20/B 34). In<br />

the Critique the notion of sensibility [Sinnlichkeit] includes both these<br />

aspects, both sensation, which is also called the matter of an intuition,<br />

and its a priori form or forms, namely time and space. In the<br />

Transcendental aesthetic both aspects are paid due attention.<br />

Does this theory also include the notion of an active mind? This<br />

seems to be clearly refuted by Kant’s definition of sensibility at A 19/B<br />

33. Here, the defining character of sensibility seems to be receptivity<br />

alone. This seems to exclude the idea that having intuitions presupposes<br />

activity. This interpretation also seems to be supported by the fact that at<br />

this point Kant seems to ascribe all activity and spontaneity to the<br />

understanding. And as sensibility and understanding are described as<br />

heterogeneous faculties, this seems to exclude the idea that our intuitions,<br />

which originate in sensibility, presuppose activity. However, rather than<br />

being the final truth, this is, I will argue, no more than an initial<br />

approach to a more comprehensive theory of intuition. As we read more<br />

of the text, the idea that having intuitions presupposes the activity of the<br />

mind becomes gradually more explicit.<br />

A first indication of this idea is found in Kant’s claim that the form of<br />

an intuition is supplied by the mind. By stating the point in this way,<br />

using the term ‘to supply’, a weak suggestion is made that the form of an<br />

intuition does in fact presuppose some kind of activity. A more<br />

explicit reference to activity is found at A 20/B 34 where Kant<br />

introduces the concept of an ‘appearance’ [Erscheinung], defined as ‘the<br />

8 This definition, or equivalents to it, is also found at other places in the Critique,<br />

cf. e.g. A 44/B 61 and A 51/B 75.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!