07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

220<br />

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> THE TRANSCENDENTAL<br />

But ‘I am simple’ signifies no more than that this representation ‘I’<br />

encompasses not the least manifoldness within itself, and that it is an<br />

absolute (though merely logical) unity. (A 355)<br />

I will not try to decide here which of the above descriptions best covers<br />

Kant’s point but I will simply repeat what I take to be his basic agenda in<br />

these passages. In analyzing self-consciousness, we never leave the field of<br />

our representations, so there is no way in which transcendental<br />

apperception may be used as a premise from which we may deduce what<br />

a human subject is qua thing in itself. A few pages later, Kant refers to<br />

this unknown and unknowable subject as ‘the transcendental subject’ (A<br />

356). 9<br />

As I see it, Kant’s concept of the transcendental subject is a clear<br />

parallel to his concept of a thing in itself. Just as our empirical<br />

representation of an object does not tell us the whole truth about what<br />

such an object is, so, according to Kant, analyzing our representations<br />

does not tell us the whole truth about who we are considered as thinking<br />

beings. In both cases, there remains something unknown that will forever<br />

remain beyond the reach of human knowledge. 10<br />

7.4 The unknown origin of affection<br />

How does Kant’s theory of embodied cognition, which I claim is implied<br />

and presupposed by the abstract discourse of the Critique, fit with Kant's<br />

transcendental idealism? As was suggested in the introduction to this<br />

chapter, there are problems involved in trying to combine these two<br />

perspectives. In this section I shall take a closer look at these problems,<br />

and then argue how they may be overcome. Let me start by focusing on<br />

Kant’s idea that sensation involves affection.<br />

According to Kant’s theory of embodied cognition (cf. e.g. the<br />

Anthropology), all sensation involves the body being affected directly or<br />

indirectly by physical objects. According to the transcendental idealism of<br />

the Critique we are justified, as part of an empirical psychology, in<br />

9<br />

See also A 354, A 355, A 381 and A 382.<br />

10<br />

This I also take to be Allison’s point (1983), 287 when he writes: ‘The Critique<br />

contains two distinct and incompatible doctrines about the relation between the<br />

subject of apperception and the noumenal self. According to one, which is Kant’s<br />

official position, the subject of apperception is identified simply with the<br />

noumenal or ‘real’ self. According to the other, which I take to express Kant’s<br />

deepest view, the subject of apperception is distinguished from the noumenal self,<br />

indeed, from any kind of intelligible object.<br />

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!