07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SPATIAL SCHEMATISM 203<br />

Indirectly the notion of obscure representations is also implied, I<br />

think, by the idea, generally advanced in the Critique that consciousness<br />

comes in degrees. This idea is mentioned in the main text, just before the<br />

footnote:<br />

For even consciousness always has a degree, which can always be<br />

diminished. (B 415)<br />

This idea is also put forward, for example, at A 175/B 217. In a passage<br />

dealing with empirical consciousness in relation to inner sense, Kant<br />

explains that this consciousness may vary in degree from zero upwards. 48<br />

Several passages in the Critique also suggest that parts of the cognitive<br />

process may take place with little consciousness. A central passage in this<br />

respect is where Kant introduces the synthetic power of the imagination,<br />

a blind force we constantly apply but normally without explicit<br />

consciousness (A 78/B 103). A similar point is stated somewhat later,<br />

arguing that all synthesis is a product of the representative faculty, he<br />

adds that this may be either conscious or unconscious (B 130). It may be<br />

confusing that Kant says that the synthetic acts of the understanding are<br />

sometimes not conscious, and if I was right earlier then no thinking, and<br />

so no synthesis, can take place without consciousness. However, I think<br />

that Kant is talking here about what we, following the distinction made<br />

at B 414-415, may call obscure consciousness, and the same applies in<br />

other cases in the Critique when he refers to unconscious cognition.<br />

Kant’s idea that consciousness comes in degrees, can also, without<br />

difficulty, be applied to embodied acts or practices. Interestingly, the<br />

Critique contains at least one example that deals explicitly with an<br />

embodied act that is performed at an obscure level of consciousness.<br />

Actually, this example occurs in the same footnote where the notion of<br />

an obscure representation is defined. The example describes the<br />

improvisations of a musician (B 415). At some level the musician has to<br />

be aware of what he is doing, Kant argues, or else he could not produce<br />

music. More precisely, without consciousness he could not make the<br />

connections and distinctions that are needed in order to produce music.<br />

However, he cannot possibly have his attention focused on every single<br />

movement of his fingers. Thus, the rapid movements of his fingers are<br />

deliberately produced and accompanied with consciousness, but on an<br />

obscure level, so that when later asked to describe these movements, he<br />

would most likely be unable to do so.<br />

48 A 175/B 217. Cf. also B 208

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!