11.07.2015 Views

The Bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an Age of Commerce

The Bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an Age of Commerce

The Bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an Age of Commerce

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

324 chapter 28other good hum<strong>an</strong> behavior depends on virtues, on hum<strong>an</strong> character. <strong>The</strong>idea is Aristoteli<strong>an</strong>. As Ralph McInerny puts it, “In the <strong>Ethics</strong>, Aristotle treatsmoral virtues first <strong>an</strong>d sees them as dispositive to <strong>an</strong>d presupposed by theintellectual virtues.” 11 Thus we observe scientists with large ethical flaws,such as the great biologist James Watson or the great statistici<strong>an</strong> Ronald A.Fisher or the great psychologist Cyril Burt or the great economist GeorgeStigler, <strong>an</strong>d are inclined to suspect their science. Our suspicions are sometimesconfirmed. On the other h<strong>an</strong>d we would be very surprised to find<strong>an</strong>ything untoward in the work <strong>of</strong> great scientists we know to be good alsoin the ethical sense, whether or not we agree with them: in biology E. O.Wilson, <strong>for</strong> example, or in economics Thomas Schelling or BarbaraBergm<strong>an</strong>n or Milton Friedm<strong>an</strong>, or in history John Hope Fr<strong>an</strong>klin orWilliam McNeill.Since 1980 a small group <strong>of</strong> philosophers have been advocating in fact“virtue epistemology.” Justified belief, as much as good behavior, they argue,depends on such virtues as “intellectual carefulness, thoroughness, humility,courage, trust, autonomy, or fairness.” 12 Elizabeth Anscombe in 1958suggested that we give up the notion <strong>of</strong> “moral duty.” “It would be a greatimprovement if, instead <strong>of</strong> ‘morally wrong,’ one always named a genus suchas ‘untruthful,’ ‘unchaste,’ ‘unjust.’” 13Similarly in epistemology Richard Rorty suggested in 1987 that we giveup “Truth,” <strong>an</strong>d substitute in a similar way the pragmatic reasons <strong>for</strong> believing.14 In a later essay, “<strong>Ethics</strong> without Principles,” he drew the <strong>an</strong>alogyexplicitly: “<strong>The</strong> trouble with aiming at truth [that is, Truth, capital T] is thatyou do not know when you have reached it, even if you had in fact reachedit. But you c<strong>an</strong> aim at ever more justification, the assuagement <strong>of</strong> ever moredoubt. Analogously, you c<strong>an</strong>not aim at ‘doing what is right,’ because you willnever know whether you have hit the mark. ...You c<strong>an</strong>not aim at being atthe end <strong>of</strong> inquiry, either in physics or in ethics.” 15 You c<strong>an</strong> make more <strong>an</strong>dmore persuasive arguments about physics or politics, <strong>an</strong>d you c<strong>an</strong> makeyourself more <strong>an</strong>d more virtuous as a physicist or citizen. <strong>The</strong> virtue epistemologistsare combining the two projects <strong>of</strong> a pragmatic epistemology <strong>an</strong>da pragmatic virtue ethics.My qu<strong>an</strong>titative, economist’s way <strong>of</strong> saying this is a little diagram. Imaginesmall-t, provisional truth in <strong>an</strong>y field <strong>of</strong> inquiry measured on the verticalaxis <strong>an</strong>d our years <strong>of</strong> patient inquiry measured along the horizontal. Atthe Second Coming I have no doubt that all will be revealed, namely, the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!