13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

98 Chapter 4. An analysis of aoristic and imperfective aspectthe maximality operator.If one assumes with de Swart (1998) and Egg (2005) that a bounded predicaterefers to a set of bounded eventualities and an unbounded predicate toa set of unbounded eventualities, one and the same eventuality cannot be <strong>in</strong>the extension of both a bounded and an unbounded predicate. A consequence<strong>for</strong> the maximality operator, which is supposed to return bounded predicates,is that no eventuality can be both <strong>in</strong> the extension of an unbounded predicateP and <strong>in</strong> the extension of the predicate that results from apply<strong>in</strong>g the maximalityoperator to P. In particular, this means that MAX cannot be used asmaximality operator, s<strong>in</strong>ce the set of eventualities to which MAX(P) refers is asubset of the set of eventualities to which bare P refers.In order to <strong>for</strong>mulate an operator that captures the idea of maximalitybut meets this requirement one often resorts to temporal or spatiotemporalequivalents of eventualities, that is, eventualities that are identical with respectto time or time and space, respectively. The idea is that, whereas it is notpossible <strong>for</strong> one and the same eventuality to be <strong>in</strong> the extension of both abounded and an unbounded predicate, it is possible that of two eventualitiesthat are (spatio)temporally identical one is <strong>in</strong> the extension of a boundedpredicate, and the other <strong>in</strong> the extension of an unbounded predicate. A naturalcandidate <strong>for</strong> a maximality operator is then (124), the dynamic equivalent ofEgg’s (2005:95) operator:e ′τ(e) = τ(e ′ )(124) MAX ′ = λPλe[e ′′e ′ ⊏ e ′′ → ¬ [ ⊕P(e ′′ )]⊕P(e ′ )]Here τ is the function that maps eventualities on their (spatio)temporal trace.Note that e is <strong>in</strong> the extension of MAX ′ (P) and e ′ , its (spatio)temporal equivalent,<strong>in</strong> that of P.There are two problems with MAX ′ , however, one more serious than theother. First, MAX ′ , <strong>in</strong> contrast to MAX, is not the identity mapp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>for</strong> boundedpredicates. It is possible that <strong>for</strong> a bounded predicate P eventualities <strong>in</strong> theextension ofMAX(P) are not <strong>in</strong> the extension ofP. This is not too problematic <strong>for</strong>my enterprise: s<strong>in</strong>ce the maximality operator functions as a coercion operatorthat comes <strong>in</strong>to play only with unbounded predicates, its effect with boundedpredicates is of no importance. What is more problematic is that MAX ′ , aga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong> contrast to MAX, need not return a bounded predicate.MAX ′ would behave the same asMAX <strong>in</strong> these two respects if we would assumethat eventualities that co<strong>in</strong>cide spatiotemporally are identical. Note, however,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!