13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

4.10 Conclusion 117In (144), some eventuality that may result <strong>in</strong> reach<strong>in</strong>g the top, but not thereach<strong>in</strong>g itself is <strong>in</strong> progress. In the same way, <strong>in</strong> (143) some eventuality thatmay result <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g killed is <strong>in</strong> progress, not the be<strong>in</strong>g killed itself. 22 Thecoercion operator <strong>in</strong>volved here maps the set of eventualities <strong>in</strong> the extensionof a predicate P onto the set of preparatory eventualities <strong>for</strong> the eventualities<strong>in</strong> the extension of P. The crucial th<strong>in</strong>g is that such an operator extends thetime associated with the predicate and thus solves the mismatch <strong>in</strong> duration.The <strong>in</strong>sertion of this coercion operator between the imperfective operator andthe predicate results <strong>in</strong> the truth conditions that the topic time is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong>a preparatory eventuality that leads to an eventuality of the k<strong>in</strong>d described bythe predicate <strong>in</strong> the normal course of eventualities: the eventuality (of dy<strong>in</strong>g,of reach<strong>in</strong>g the top) ‘was about to happen’. S<strong>in</strong>ce the subject <strong>in</strong> (143) <strong>in</strong>contrast to (144) supposedly doesn’t want the eventuality to happen, we getthe <strong>in</strong>terpretation that it threatened to happen. 23 To conclude this discussionof the likelihood <strong>in</strong>terpretation I emphasise that we need the <strong>in</strong>tensional IMP ′rather than IMP to avoid be<strong>in</strong>g committed to the existence of an actual dy<strong>in</strong>gor reach<strong>in</strong>g eventuality.In this section I have argued that the conative and likelihood <strong>in</strong>terpretations<strong>in</strong> <strong>Ancient</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> should be understood <strong>in</strong> the same terms as the effects foundwith the comb<strong>in</strong>ation of the progressive with bounded and punctual predicates<strong>in</strong> English.4.10 ConclusionLet me recapitulate my account of the various <strong>in</strong>terpretations of aoristic andimperfective aspect, which is also graphically represented <strong>in</strong> Figure 4.15. Theaorist and imperfective are grammatical aspects and determ<strong>in</strong>e the relationbetween the topic time and the eventuality time. More specifically, the aorist<strong>in</strong>dicates that the eventuality time is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time, the imperfectivethat the eventuality time <strong>in</strong>cludes the topic time. This semantics of aorist22 If one prefers to classify I be killed as a non-punctual predicate, that’s f<strong>in</strong>e with me too.Then the be<strong>in</strong>g killed itself (which now consists of several phases) is <strong>in</strong> progress, which yieldsthe same <strong>in</strong>terpretation as the account given here where the preparatory eventuality of apunctual eventuality is <strong>in</strong> progress. Similarly, I wouldn’t have a problem with classify<strong>in</strong>gDarius buy the garment as punctual, referr<strong>in</strong>g to the sole moment of giv<strong>in</strong>g the money, andsay<strong>in</strong>g that preparatory coercion is <strong>in</strong>volved here, s<strong>in</strong>ce the result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terpretation is thesame.23 The duration associated with the predicate is not the only factor that determ<strong>in</strong>eswhether a sentence is traditionally classified as an example of the conative or of the likelihood<strong>in</strong>terpretation. Other properties of the predicate play a role as well, <strong>for</strong> examplewhether the subject is an <strong>in</strong>tentional agent. If it is, as <strong>in</strong> (135), the example is classified asconative. If it’s not, as <strong>in</strong> (143), we may get the <strong>in</strong>terpretation that someth<strong>in</strong>g threatenedto occur. From an aspectual po<strong>in</strong>t of view, however, this difference is not relevant.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!