13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

4.4 Selectional restriction of the aorist 85the predicate, and, hence, from the existence of an eventuality that makes anunbounded predicate true and that is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time, it cannot beconcluded that the maximal eventuality is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time as well.This is illustrated on the left-hand side of Figure 4.5. The dotted l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>dicatesthe possibility of a larger eventuality to which the predicate applies.aoristimperfectivetopic timeeventuality time. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .Figure 4.5: Aorist and imperfective with unbounded predicatesSo, on the basis of its semantics (101b) we would expect that the aoristcan also be used if the maximal eventuality <strong>in</strong>cludes the topic time, as longas some eventuality of the right k<strong>in</strong>d is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time. This,however, is not the case. Hence, <strong>for</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of completion withunbounded predicates, the semantics of the aorist (101b) does not suffice. The<strong>in</strong>terpretation we want to get is that the maximal eventuality is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong>the topic time, whereas the semantics gives us only that some eventuality is<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time.This problem can be solved by restrict<strong>in</strong>g the aorist to bounded predicates.This means that if the aorist is confronted with an unbounded predicate, a coercionoperator comes <strong>in</strong>to play that maps the unbounded predicate onto abounded one. In the next section we will see that one of these coercion operators,the maximality operator, yields the complexive <strong>in</strong>terpretation. ThereI will also show that a restriction of the aorist to bounded predicates at thesame time expla<strong>in</strong>s the restriction of the <strong>in</strong>gressive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the aoristto unbounded predicates.The right-hand side of Figure 4.5 shows that <strong>for</strong> imperfective aspect thesemantics given <strong>in</strong> (101a) is enough to yield the processual <strong>in</strong>terpretation, evenwith unbounded predicates. For it may be that the eventuality that <strong>in</strong>cludesthe topic time is not maximal with respect to the predicate, but this makes nodifference <strong>for</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretation: the maximal eventuality will also <strong>in</strong>clude thetopic time, so we still get the <strong>in</strong>terpretation that the eventuality is go<strong>in</strong>g on.Now that I have shown that the semantics of the aorist (101b) is not enoughto account <strong>for</strong> the data and argued that add<strong>in</strong>g an aspectual class restrictionwould be useful, it is time to ask where this restriction comes from. What is

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!