13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

4.5 Aorist and coercion: the <strong>in</strong>gressive and complexive <strong>in</strong>terpretations 874.5 Aorist and coercion: the <strong>in</strong>gressive andcomplexive <strong>in</strong>terpretationsIn section 4.3 I proposed a semantics <strong>for</strong> aoristic and imperfective aspect thatdirectly yields the completive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the <strong>for</strong>mer and the processual<strong>in</strong>terpretation of the latter. In this section I will tackle the <strong>in</strong>gressive andcomplexive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of aoristic aspect. Section 4.7 is devoted to thehabitual <strong>in</strong>terpretation of imperfective aspect and <strong>in</strong> section 4.9 we turn to theconative and likelihood <strong>in</strong>terpretation of this aspect.Actually, we already have all the <strong>in</strong>gredients <strong>for</strong> the analysis of these <strong>in</strong>terpretations.The analysis consists of (i) the semantics of aoristic and imperfectiveaspect (section 4.3), (ii) the selectional restriction of the aorist <strong>for</strong>bounded predicates (section 4.4), and (iii) Egg’s Duration Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple (section3.3.3). We just have to put them together.In section 2.1 we have seen that with unbounded predicates, the aoristmay have an <strong>in</strong>gressive and a complexive <strong>in</strong>terpretation. I propose that these<strong>in</strong>terpretations emerge as an attempt to avoid an threaten<strong>in</strong>g mismatch betweenthe selectional restriction of the aorist <strong>for</strong> bounded predicates and theaspectual class of its argument.Let me illustrate how this works. The selectional restriction of the aorist<strong>for</strong> bounded predicates causes re<strong>in</strong>terpretation when the aorist is confrontedwith an unbounded predicate. The mismatch between the restriction of theoperator, AOR, and its argument, the predicate, is avoided by the <strong>in</strong>terventionof coercion operators that map unbounded predicates onto bounded predicates.As a result the complexive and <strong>in</strong>gressive <strong>in</strong>terpretations arise.The <strong>for</strong>mer <strong>in</strong>terpretation, the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of completion with unboundedpredicates, is obta<strong>in</strong>ed by the use of a coercion operator that maps the set ofeventualities <strong>in</strong> the extension of a predicate P onto the set of locally maximalP eventualities. This is exactly what AOR ′ , the simpler version of Krifka’s(1989b) AOR, does (cf. section 3.2.2). To avoid confusion (I don’t use AOR ′ <strong>for</strong>the semantics of the aorist itself) I rename the operator MAX.(110) MAX = λPλe[ e ′e ⊏ e ′ → ¬ [ ⊕P(e ′ )]⊕P(e)]Its effect is illustrated <strong>in</strong> Figure 4.7. Imag<strong>in</strong>e that e 1 is a sleep<strong>in</strong>g eventualityof John from the moment he falls asleep to the moment he wakes up, andthat e 2 , e 3 , and e 4 are parts of this eventuality. These parts are themselves alsosleep<strong>in</strong>g eventualities of John. They are not maximal sleep<strong>in</strong>g eventualities of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!