13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3.2 The perfective-imperfective dist<strong>in</strong>ction 41element(i), (ii), and (iii) together make the structure a jo<strong>in</strong> semi-lattice and (iv)ensures that there is no bottom element.A part-of relation ⊑ can be def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> terms of the operation ⊔:(57) e ⊑ e ′ iff e ⊔ e ′ = e ′The proper part-of relation is then def<strong>in</strong>ed as follows:(58) e ⊏ e ′ iff e ⊑ e ′ and e ≠ e ′Krifka def<strong>in</strong>es the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between telic and atelic predicates <strong>for</strong>mallywith the use of this proper part-of relation. He claims that telic predicates arequantised: 14(59) A property P is quantised iff <strong>for</strong> all e, e ′ if P(e) and e ′ ⊏ e then ¬P(e ′ )A predicate is quantised iff no eventuality that is a proper part of an eventuality<strong>in</strong> the extension of the predicate is also <strong>in</strong> its extension. For example, a properpart of an eventuality <strong>in</strong> the extension of the telic predicate John build a houseis not likewise <strong>in</strong> the extension of John build a house (<strong>in</strong> the same way as aproper part of a bottle of water does not count aga<strong>in</strong> as a bottle of water).Atelic predicates, on the other hand, are non-quantised (often called homogeneous).The predicate John walk, <strong>for</strong> example, is non-quantised, given thata part of an eventuality <strong>in</strong> the extension of this predicate is <strong>in</strong> its extensiontoo, except when the parts get too small to count as walk<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong> the same wayas a part of water still counts as water, up to the level of molecules). Krifkaseems to require moreover that atelic predicates are cumulative. 15 I postponethe discussion of cumulativity to a later po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> this section.With this <strong>for</strong>malisation of telicity Krifka immediately derives a numberof phenomena that needed some stipulations <strong>in</strong> the DRT accounts discussed<strong>in</strong> the previous section. Let’s first consider the <strong>in</strong>teraction with time-frameadverbials like on Sunday.(60) a. Mary wrote a letter on Sunday.b. Mary was ill on Sunday.c. Mary wrote on Sunday14 Strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g, quanticity is a property of properties, and a predicate is quantised <strong>in</strong>a derived sense only, viz. if it denotes a quantised property.15 Krifka (1989a:90): “Basically, telic predicates can be reconstructed as quantised eventpredicates, and atelic predicates as event predicates which are strictly cumulative (or atleast, non-quantised).” Krifka (1989b:158): “Die Atelizität wird umgekehrt durch die Kumulativitätdes verbalen Prädikats erfaßt werden.” (“Atelicity, by contrast, will be capturedby the cumulativity of the verbal predicate.”)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!