13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

112 Chapter 4. An analysis of aoristic and imperfective aspecthowever, s<strong>in</strong>ce if we wish, we can easily <strong>in</strong>tensionalise the semantics of theaorist as well:(139) AOR ′ = λPλt w ′Inert t (w 0 ,w ′ ) → [eτ(e) ⊆ t ⊕P(w′ )(e)]The result, however, is identical to what we get with the simple semantics,proposed earlier. S<strong>in</strong>ce all <strong>in</strong>ertia worlds are identical to the actual world untilthe end of the topic time, it follows from the fact that there is a P eventuality<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time <strong>in</strong> all <strong>in</strong>ertia worlds that there is such an eventuality<strong>in</strong> the actual world.The <strong>for</strong>ego<strong>in</strong>g discussion shows how Dowty’s solution of the imperfectiveparadox can be <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong> the semantics of imperfective and aoristic aspect.In order to keep <strong>for</strong>mulas simple, I will return to the simple, non-<strong>in</strong>tensionalsemantics <strong>for</strong> the rema<strong>in</strong>der of this work. It should be noted that this hasno effect on the proposed analyses as they can all be re<strong>for</strong>mulated <strong>in</strong> the<strong>in</strong>tensional semantics without affect<strong>in</strong>g the results. 18Be<strong>for</strong>e we leave the subject of the imperfective paradox, I will discuss adifferent way to avoid this paradox, proposed by Gerö and von Stechow (2003).It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to see how they deal with the paradox, s<strong>in</strong>ce I have adoptedtheir semantics of imperfective and aoristic aspect. I will try to show that ananalysis along the l<strong>in</strong>es described above is superior to their account.The imperfective paradox is probably the reason why Gerö and von Stechow(2003) propose their selectional restriction of imperfective aspect to unboundedpredicates (see section 3.2.4). The (implicit) reason<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d this restrictionseems to be the follow<strong>in</strong>g: The problem of the imperfective paradox arises onlywith bounded predicates. By restrict<strong>in</strong>g imperfective aspect to unboundedpredicates, no problem will arise.But then the question is what to do with the cases where the imperfectiveseem<strong>in</strong>gly comb<strong>in</strong>es with a bounded predicate. The straight<strong>for</strong>ward answer isto <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>for</strong> these cases a coercion operator that maps the bounded predicateonto an unbounded predicate. For this purpose, Gerö and von Stechow(2003) propose the operator PROG ′ which, like my IMP ′ , is based on Dowty’s(1979) semantics <strong>for</strong> the English progressive: 1918 This also holds <strong>for</strong> examples that <strong>in</strong>volve habitual coercion, s<strong>in</strong>ce a proper habitualityoperator returns unbounded predicates.19 I have re<strong>for</strong>mulated their account <strong>in</strong> DRT and adapted the use of variables to my ownnotational conventions.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!