13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6.3 Analys<strong>in</strong>g the patterns 141has been previously <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> the discourse. 4,5 It is <strong>for</strong> this very reasonthat I have adopted the dynamic framework of DRT. As a consequence of thetopic time be<strong>in</strong>g an anaphor, the time to which t TTi b<strong>in</strong>ds, that is, by defaulta time immediately follow<strong>in</strong>g τ(e) i−1 if sentence i–1 has aoristic aspect,has to be made available <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretation process of sentence i–1 already.This is done <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way: an aoristic sentence <strong>in</strong>troduces not only theeventuality it describes <strong>in</strong>to the discourse context, but also a new time, whichfollows the eventuality and acts as the default topic time <strong>for</strong> the eventuality ofthe new sentence. Imperfective sentences do not <strong>in</strong>troduce such a subsequentpo<strong>in</strong>t. They pass their own topic time on to the next sentence. Thus aoristic,but not imperfective, aspect pushes the topic time further, so to speak. Accountslike this one are called push<strong>in</strong>g accounts. Earlier examples of push<strong>in</strong>gaccounts are the ones of H<strong>in</strong>richs (1981, 1986) and Partee (1984) <strong>for</strong> English,to which the present one comes quite close. 6This account deviates from the account of Kamp et al., discussed <strong>in</strong> section3.2.1, <strong>in</strong> several respects. Their account is a pull<strong>in</strong>g rather than push<strong>in</strong>g account.On pull<strong>in</strong>g accounts sentences do not push the time <strong>for</strong>ward. Moreover,not the topic time itself, but the reference po<strong>in</strong>t, is treated as an anaphor. Recallthat tense on their account <strong>in</strong>troduces the <strong>in</strong>struction to temporally relatethe location time of the eventuality at hand to a time previously mentioned <strong>in</strong>the discourse. Thus, two elements have to be resolved: the reference po<strong>in</strong>t hasto be determ<strong>in</strong>ed and the temporal relation has to be specified. The referencepo<strong>in</strong>t is by default the location time of the last mentioned eventuality, thetemporal relation is succession <strong>for</strong> events, and <strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>for</strong> states.The two types of accounts expla<strong>in</strong> the phenomenon of narrative progression<strong>in</strong> different ways. Let me illustrate the difference with (169) (=(40)):4 It has been argued that tenses cannot be treated as anaphors <strong>in</strong> general. The behaviourof tense <strong>in</strong> attitude reports has been put <strong>for</strong>ward as a counterexample to the anaphoricnature of tense (e.g. von Stechow 1995). This is due to the fact that tense <strong>in</strong>terpretation<strong>in</strong> such contexts <strong>in</strong>volves egocentric de se b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g (Lewis 1979), which <strong>for</strong>ms a tension withanaphoricity <strong>in</strong> most frameworks. Bary and Maier (2009) show, however, that tenses <strong>in</strong>attitude reports are anaphoric just as well and propose an extension of DRT <strong>in</strong> which thetension between the two features of tense <strong>in</strong>terpretation is resolved. In this extension updatesof the common ground are accompanied by updates of each relevant agent’s attitud<strong>in</strong>al state.The proposed framework can capture both the de se feature and the anaphoric feature oftense <strong>in</strong>terpretation at the same time and thus shows that the behaviour of tense <strong>in</strong> attitudereports is not a counterexample to the anaphoric nature of tense. See also Kamp (2006).5 In this context it is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to note that accord<strong>in</strong>g to Ruijgh (1991:212, n. 10) andBeekes (1995:226) the past tense morpheme (the augment - e-) probably comes from atemporal anaphoric pronoun with the value ‘at that time’.6 One difference is that <strong>in</strong> the present account it’s grammatical aspect that determ<strong>in</strong>eswhether a new time is <strong>in</strong>troduced to act as topic time <strong>for</strong> the next sentence, whereas <strong>in</strong>H<strong>in</strong>rich’s and Partee’s accounts this is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by aspectual class (that is, whether thesentence describes an event or state).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!