13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

86 Chapter 4. An analysis of aoristic and imperfective aspectthe rationale beh<strong>in</strong>d it? This question Gerö and von Stechow (2003) don’t givean answer to. Instead, they simply state that the aspectual class restrictionfollows from the semantics of the aorist (see section 3.2.4).I claim that the rationale beh<strong>in</strong>d the proposed restriction of the aorist tobounded predicates is that without this restriction some situations describableby the imperfective of a predicate P could be expressed us<strong>in</strong>g the aorist of P aswell. This would be the case when an eventuality e to whose runtime IMP(P)applies has at least one part e ′ that is also <strong>in</strong> the extension of P and this secondeventuality is so small that its runtime is located with<strong>in</strong> the topic time. Figure4.6 illustrates this situation. In this situation the imperfective of P can be usedt TTτ(e)τ(e ′ )Figure 4.6: Overlap between aorist and imperfective with unbounded predicatesas there is a P eventuality whose runtime <strong>in</strong>cludes the topic time, viz. e. Butwithout further constra<strong>in</strong>t the aorist could be used, as well, <strong>for</strong> there is also aP eventuality whose runtime is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the topic time, viz. e ′ .This unwanted potential overlap between imperfective and aorist is ruledout if the aorist is restricted to bounded predicates. Eventually, this restrictionrepresents an <strong>in</strong>stance of ‘pragmatic strengthen<strong>in</strong>g’, which removes semanticoverlap between compet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stantiations of the same grammatical feature(here, aspect) (compare this <strong>for</strong> example with the division of labour betweendef<strong>in</strong>ite and <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite NPs as proposed by Hawk<strong>in</strong>s 1991). In contrast, theimperfective does not restrict the aspectual class of its argument.Of course, this restriction of aoristic aspect to bounded predicates does notmean that the aorist does not occur with unbounded predicates. Actually,we have seen examples of the aorist with unbounded predicates <strong>in</strong> section2.1 (examples (19) to (21)). Rather, it means that <strong>in</strong> those cases a literal<strong>in</strong>terpretation is not available and re<strong>in</strong>terpretation is needed <strong>in</strong> order to makesense of the sentence. More specifically, the unbounded predicate must bere<strong>in</strong>terpreted as a bounded predicate. In the next section I will show thatsuch re<strong>in</strong>terpretations can be analysed as the result of coercion operators that<strong>in</strong>tervene between the semantics of the aorist and its argument. The <strong>in</strong>gressiveand complexive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the aorist will be shown to come about <strong>in</strong> thisway.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!