13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

4.2 <strong>Aspect</strong>ual classes 77stative predicate like John be <strong>in</strong> the pub is true of an eventuality e, it is trueof all eventualities that are part of e. Non-stative predicates like John waltzdo not have this property, s<strong>in</strong>ce an eventuality has to consist of at least threesteps be<strong>for</strong>e it counts as a John waltz eventuality. They are what Egg (2005)calls <strong>in</strong>terval-based. I def<strong>in</strong>e stativity as follows:(100) A property P is stative iff (i) <strong>for</strong> all e, e ′ if P(e) and e ′ ⊏ e thenP(e ′ ), and (ii) it is not the case that <strong>for</strong> all e such that P(e) there isno e ′ such that e ′ ⊏ eThe first clause, based on Egg’s (2005:59) def<strong>in</strong>ition of <strong>in</strong>terval-basedness,captures the above-mentioned idea that stative predicates are fully divisive,whereas non-stative predicates are not. The second clause adds that stativepredicates are non-punctual, that is, some eventualities <strong>in</strong> the extension ofsuch a predicate have parts. The addition of this clause guarantees that allbounded predicates are non-stative. Without it, punctual predicates (predicatesthat apply only to eventualities without parts) would be both boundedand stative.Table 4.1 shows the tripartition <strong>in</strong>duced by these two properties of predicates.We have stative predicates, bounded predicates, and predicates thatare unbounded but non-stative, <strong>for</strong> which I use the term process predicates <strong>in</strong>l<strong>in</strong>e with de Swart.stativenon-stativeunboundedboundedstativeprocessboundedTable 4.1: <strong>Aspect</strong>ual classes of predicatesIn my analysis of aoristic and imperfective aspect only the property ofboundedness plays a role (sections 4.4 and 4.5). I need the property of stativity<strong>for</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g the English progressive and the <strong>Greek</strong> imperfective (section 4.8).In my classification I only classify predicates of eventualities, not eventualitiesthemselves. In this respect, I follow Krifka and deviate from, <strong>for</strong> example,de Swart and Egg, who assume different sorts of eventualities on top of adist<strong>in</strong>ction at the predicate level. In the latter accounts bounded predicates,<strong>for</strong> example, have the property described <strong>in</strong> (99) and also refer to a set ofbounded eventualities. My first problem with such an approach is that it isnot clear to me which criterion has primacy <strong>in</strong> such accounts: is a predicatebounded because it has the property <strong>in</strong> (99) or because it refers to a set ofbounded eventualities? My second objection is that I don’t see why we needan ontological dist<strong>in</strong>ction on top of the dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>for</strong> predicates, at least not

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!