13.07.2015 Views

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Aspect in Ancient Greek - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

4.9 The conative and likelihood <strong>in</strong>terpretations 107the fact that imperfective and aoristic aspect make a semantic contributionwith any predicate. With aspectually neutral <strong>for</strong>ms the eventuality would notbe related to the topic time. The progressive, on the other hand, does notdeterm<strong>in</strong>e the relation to the topic time. Given its semantics <strong>in</strong> (132) it doesnot make a semantic contribution with stative predicates and as a result issuperfluous.One may raise the follow<strong>in</strong>g objection to this explanation of why the imperfective,<strong>in</strong> contrast to the progressive, does comb<strong>in</strong>e with stative predicates:the reason that the imperfective does comb<strong>in</strong>e with stative predicates is that <strong>in</strong><strong>Greek</strong>, <strong>in</strong> contrast to English, there are no aspectually neutral <strong>for</strong>ms that couldbe chosen <strong>in</strong>stead. Note, however, that my explanation goes further as it expla<strong>in</strong>swhy there are no aspectually neutral <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ancient</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>, the reasonbe<strong>in</strong>g that the imperfective and aorist always make a semantic contribution.4.9 The conative and likelihood <strong>in</strong>terpretationsAfter the discussion of the <strong>in</strong>teraction between imperfective aspect and stativepredicates <strong>in</strong> the previous section, let’s now turn to the <strong>in</strong>teraction withbounded predicates. Imperfective aspect <strong>in</strong>dicates that an eventuality describedby the predicate is go<strong>in</strong>g on at the time about which we speak, thetopic time. Intuitively, this semantics can handle the conative <strong>in</strong>terpretationof imperfective aspect, the use of imperfective aspect <strong>for</strong> eventualities that donot proceed further than an attempt (see section 2.1), which is restricted tobounded predicates. The <strong>in</strong>tuitive explanation of this use is as follows: S<strong>in</strong>ceone restricts one’s claim to a specific time and says about that time that aneventuality is go<strong>in</strong>g on, no claim is made that the eventuality will ever becompleted. For stative predicates this is not relevant, given that a part of aneventuality that makes a stative predicate true also makes the predicate true(cf. (100)). So even if the eventuality is not completed, there is still an eventualityto which the predicate applies. To a high degree, the same holds <strong>for</strong>unbounded non-stative predicates, due to their partial divisivity (cf. (99) and(100)). 15 But <strong>for</strong> bounded predicates (cf. (99)), it is not the case that if thereis an eventuality of the relevant k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> progress there is also an eventuality towhich the predicate applies. To illustrate this, compare the French examples<strong>in</strong> (133) and (134):(133) a. Max c o u r a i t.Max run.pst.IPFV.3sg“Max was runn<strong>in</strong>g”15 That it is a high degree can be concluded from the fact that (133a) entails (133b): anarbitrary part of runn<strong>in</strong>g still counts as runn<strong>in</strong>g.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!