12.12.2012 Views

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

156 brains<br />

more about <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>ir reason for taking <strong>the</strong> plane (e.g., going on a business<br />

trip or on vacation), <strong>the</strong>ir mood, etc.<br />

Originally, <strong>the</strong> term empathy was translated by Titchener (1908) from<br />

<strong>the</strong> German term Einfühlung. In <strong>the</strong> texts of 19th-century German philosophers<br />

and psychologists, like <strong>The</strong>odor Lipps (1903), Einfühlung was used to<br />

designate an implicit process of knowledge, different from <strong>the</strong> rational mode<br />

of knowledge, which gave access to <strong>the</strong> es<strong>the</strong>tic or <strong>the</strong> emotional content of<br />

a situation. <strong>The</strong> viewer of a painting or <strong>the</strong> listener to a piece of music, for<br />

example, resented its beauty not through an act of perception but, ra<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

through a modification of his or her own emotional state. <strong>The</strong> same concept<br />

of empathy eventually became used in <strong>the</strong> context of clinical psychology<br />

(see Pigman, 1995). Lipps considered empathy to be <strong>the</strong> source of<br />

knowledge about o<strong>the</strong>r individuals, to <strong>the</strong> same extent as sensory perception<br />

is <strong>the</strong> source of knowledge about objects. His idea was that we understand,<br />

for example, facial expressions displayed by o<strong>the</strong>r persons not because<br />

we compare <strong>the</strong>m with our own expressions, which we cannot see, but because<br />

<strong>the</strong> vision of an expression on <strong>the</strong> face of someone else “awakens [in<br />

<strong>the</strong> observer] impulses to such movements that are suited to call just this<br />

expression into existence” (Lipps, 1903, p. 193; see Pigman, 1995). Note<br />

that empathy, as defined here by Lipps, fits <strong>the</strong> concept of communication<br />

between individuals at <strong>the</strong> level of embodied selves ra<strong>the</strong>r than of narrative<br />

selves, a distinction which was <strong>the</strong> starting point of this paper.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concept of empathy, and its consequences for behavior, is taken by<br />

<strong>the</strong> simulation <strong>the</strong>orists as equivalent to mind reading, <strong>the</strong> ability for normal<br />

people to understand and predict <strong>the</strong> behavior of <strong>the</strong>ir conspecifics, which<br />

we mentioned earlier. Gallese and Goldman (1998) proceeded one step<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r in proposing an explanation of mind reading in terms of brain mechanisms:<br />

<strong>the</strong>y proposed that <strong>the</strong> observed behavior would activate, in <strong>the</strong><br />

observer’s brain, <strong>the</strong> same mechanisms that would be activated were that<br />

behavior intended or imagined by <strong>the</strong> observer. <strong>The</strong>y state that “when one<br />

is observing <strong>the</strong> action of ano<strong>the</strong>r, one undergoes a neural event that is qualitatively<br />

<strong>the</strong> same as [<strong>the</strong>] event that triggers actual movement in <strong>the</strong> observed<br />

agent” and, thus, “a mind-reader represents an actor’s behavior by<br />

recreating in himself <strong>the</strong> plans or movement intentions of <strong>the</strong> actor.” Gallese<br />

and Goldman’s view is close to that heralded in <strong>the</strong> field of linguistics to<br />

account for perception of speech by a listener: <strong>the</strong> general idea is that <strong>the</strong><br />

listener would implicitly repeat <strong>the</strong> auditory message and access <strong>the</strong> spoken<br />

message via a subliminal activation of his neural and muscular speech mechanisms<br />

(<strong>the</strong> so-called motor <strong>the</strong>ory of speech perception; Liberman &<br />

Mattingly, 1985). Thus, <strong>the</strong> simulation <strong>the</strong>ory would encompass a number<br />

of propositions coming from different fields, with <strong>the</strong> common aim of<br />

explaining communication between people.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!