12.12.2012 Views

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

architectural basis of affect 219<br />

Now suppose that <strong>the</strong>re are some situations in which an overall damping<br />

of action is adaptive: for instance, hibernation, being in <strong>the</strong> presence of a dominant<br />

conspecific, or having a brutal parent who reacts violently on <strong>the</strong> slightest<br />

provocation. <strong>The</strong> adaptivity of restricting actions in such situations might<br />

result in <strong>the</strong> evolution of a damping mechanism, D, that, when activated, globally<br />

reduces <strong>the</strong> possibilities for action, via internal controls. So, when <strong>the</strong><br />

system detects a situation in which such damping would be advantageous, this<br />

produces state P (an example of a mood) where P reliably activates D, which<br />

in turn both activates or enhances <strong>the</strong> negative affective state N and enhances<br />

P. While those conditions in which damping is advantageous persist, P would<br />

be a positively affective state: it can be desirable to lie low in a dangerous situation<br />

even though it is not desirable to be in a dangerous situation and lying<br />

low is not normally desirable (e.g., when hungry). So, <strong>the</strong>re will be a conflict<br />

between P, whose function is to reduce activity, and N, whose function is to<br />

increase possibilities for action; but P wins in certain circumstances. In some<br />

cases, positive feedback mechanisms could make it very difficult to break out<br />

of P, even after <strong>the</strong> initiating conditions have been removed and continuation<br />

of damping would no longer be advantageous.<br />

<strong>The</strong> actual nature of depression is probably far more complex; this<br />

explanatory sketch is offered only to show that <strong>the</strong>re is no incompatibility,<br />

in principle, between complex states like depression and our analysis<br />

of affect.<br />

Incidentally, this explanation sketch also shows that what we call positively<br />

or negatively affective states need not be consciously experienced as<br />

pleasant or unpleasant. In fact, <strong>the</strong> state itself need not be recognized, even<br />

though some of its consequences are.<br />

Crucial to this explanation is <strong>the</strong> fact that if two affective substates coexist,<br />

one positive and one negative (or if <strong>the</strong>re are two positive or two negative<br />

affective states that tend to produce conflicting actions), <strong>the</strong>ir effects<br />

do not in general “sum up” or “cancel out” as if <strong>the</strong>y were coexisting physical<br />

forces. It is even possible for one substate to have <strong>the</strong> specific function<br />

of disabling <strong>the</strong> normal effects of ano<strong>the</strong>r, for instance, when being paralyzed<br />

by fear prevents <strong>the</strong> normal escape behavior that would reveal one’s<br />

location, as in freezing in rats. More generally, vector summation is often<br />

not suitable ei<strong>the</strong>r for combining <strong>the</strong> effects of coexisting affective states or<br />

for dealing with conflicts. Instead of summing, it is normally sensible to select<br />

one from a set of desirable but incompatible actions since any “summing”<br />

could produce disastrous effects, like Buridan’s proverbial ass placed halfway<br />

between food and drink. More intelligent organisms may invent ways<br />

of satisfying two initially incompatible desires, instead of merely selecting<br />

one of <strong>the</strong>m.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!