12.12.2012 Views

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

architectural basis of affect 209<br />

shame, melancholy, and so on—are grouped under this term that<br />

it is dubious that <strong>the</strong>y share anything but a family resemblance.<br />

(Delancey, 2002) 2<br />

<strong>The</strong> phenomena are even more disparate than that suggests. For instance,<br />

some people would describe an insect as having emotions such as fear, anger,<br />

or being startled, whereas o<strong>the</strong>rs would deny <strong>the</strong> possibility. Worse still, when<br />

people disagree as to whe<strong>the</strong>r something does or does not have emotions (e.g.,<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r a fetus can suffer), <strong>the</strong>y often disagree on what would count as evidence<br />

to settle <strong>the</strong> question. For instance, some, but not all, consider that<br />

behavioral responses determine <strong>the</strong> answer; o<strong>the</strong>rs require certain neural<br />

mechanisms to have developed; and some say it is merely a matter of degree<br />

and some that it is not a factual matter at all but a matter for ethical decision.<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong> well-documented conceptual unclarity, many researchers<br />

still assume that <strong>the</strong> word emotion refers to a generally understood and fairly<br />

precisely defined collection of mechanisms, processes, or states. For <strong>the</strong>m,<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r (some) robots should or could have emotions is a well-defined<br />

question. However, if <strong>the</strong>re really is no clear, well-defined, widely understood<br />

concept, it is not worth attempting to answer <strong>the</strong> question until we<br />

have achieved more conceptual clarity.<br />

Detailed analysis of pre<strong>the</strong>oretical concepts (folk psychology) can make<br />

progress using <strong>the</strong> methods of conceptual analysis explained in Chapter 4<br />

of Sloman (1978), based on Austin (1956). However, that is not our main<br />

purpose.<br />

Arguing about what emotions really are is pointless: “emotion” is a cluster<br />

concept (Sloman, 2002), which has some clear instances (e.g., violent anger),<br />

some clear non-instances (e.g., remembering a ma<strong>the</strong>matical formula), and a<br />

host of indeterminate cases on which agreement cannot easily be reached.<br />

However, something all <strong>the</strong> various phenomena called emotions seem to have<br />

in common is membership of a more general category of phenomena that are<br />

often called affective, e.g., desires, likes, dislikes, drives, preferences, pleasures,<br />

pains, values, ideals, attitudes, concerns, interests, moods, intentions, etc., <strong>the</strong><br />

more enduring of which can be thought of as components of personality, as<br />

suggested by Ortony (2002; see also chapter 7, Ortony et al.).<br />

Mental phenomena that would not be classified as affective include<br />

perceiving, learning, thinking, reasoning, wondering whe<strong>the</strong>r, noticing,<br />

remembering, imagining, planning, attending, selecting, acting, changing<br />

one’s mind, stopping or altering an action, and so on. We shall try to clarify<br />

this distinction below.<br />

It may be that many who are interested in emotions are, unwittingly, interested<br />

in <strong>the</strong> more general phenomena of affect (Ortony, 2002). This would<br />

account for some of <strong>the</strong> overgeneral applications of <strong>the</strong> label “emotion.”

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!