12.12.2012 Views

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

how do we decipher o<strong>the</strong>rs’ minds? 159<br />

<strong>the</strong> self or not. One network would be involved with recognizing actions as<br />

belonging to <strong>the</strong> self, and ano<strong>the</strong>r would correspond to attributing actions<br />

to ano<strong>the</strong>r person. We know from <strong>the</strong> results described above that brain areas<br />

activated during self-produced actions (executed or not) and when observing<br />

actions of o<strong>the</strong>r people partly overlap: this is <strong>the</strong> basis for <strong>the</strong> concept of<br />

shared representations, introduced by Daprati et al. (1997) and Georgieff and<br />

Jeannerod (1998), according to which different mental states concerning<br />

actions (e.g., intending an action and observing it from ano<strong>the</strong>r person) share<br />

<strong>the</strong> same neural representations yet still have distinct patterns of neural<br />

activity.<br />

To clarify this concept, let us briefly describe experimental results obtained<br />

from monkeys. A dramatic example of a shared representation is offered<br />

by <strong>the</strong> finding of mirror neurons (Rizzolatti, Fadiga, Gallese, & Fogassi,<br />

1995). Mirror neurons were identified in <strong>the</strong> monkey premotor cortex. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

are activated in two conditions: first, <strong>the</strong>y fire when <strong>the</strong> animal is involved<br />

in a specific motor action, like picking a piece of food with a precision grip;<br />

second, <strong>the</strong>y also fire when <strong>the</strong> immobile animal watches <strong>the</strong> same action<br />

performed by an external agent (ano<strong>the</strong>r monkey or an experimenter). In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, mirror neurons represent one particular type of action, irrespective<br />

of <strong>the</strong> agent who performs it. At this point, it could be suspected<br />

that <strong>the</strong> signal produced by <strong>the</strong>se neurons, and exploited by o<strong>the</strong>r elements<br />

downstream in <strong>the</strong> information-processing flow, would be <strong>the</strong> same for<br />

actions performed by <strong>the</strong> self and by ano<strong>the</strong>r agent: <strong>the</strong> two modalities of<br />

that action (executed and observed) would thus have <strong>the</strong> same neural representation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem of actor identification, however, is solved by <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that o<strong>the</strong>r premotor neurons (<strong>the</strong> canonical neurons), and presumably<br />

many o<strong>the</strong>r neuron populations, fire only when <strong>the</strong> monkey performs <strong>the</strong><br />

action and not when it observes it from ano<strong>the</strong>r agent. This is indeed ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

critical feature of <strong>the</strong> shared representations concept: representations<br />

overlap only partially, and <strong>the</strong> nonoverlapping part of a given representation<br />

can be <strong>the</strong> cue for attributing <strong>the</strong> action to <strong>the</strong> self or to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong><br />

same mechanism operates in humans. <strong>Brain</strong> activity during different conditions<br />

where subjects were simulating actions (e.g., intending actions and<br />

preparing for execution, imagining actions, or observing actions performed<br />

by o<strong>the</strong>r people) was compared (Decety et al., 1994, 1997; Grafton, Arbib,<br />

Fadiga, & Rizzolatti, 1996; Rizzolatti et al., 1996; Gérardin et al., 2000). <strong>The</strong><br />

outcome of <strong>the</strong>se studies is twofold: first, <strong>the</strong>re exists a cortical network<br />

common to all conditions, to which <strong>the</strong> inferior parietal lobule (areas 39 and<br />

40), <strong>the</strong> ventral premotor area (ventral area 6), and part of supplementary<br />

motor area contribute; second, motor representations for each individual<br />

condition are clearly specified by <strong>the</strong> activation of cortical zones which do<br />

not overlap between conditions (Ruby & Decéty, 2001).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!