12.12.2012 Views

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

Who Needs Emotions? The Brain Meets the Robot

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

a social cognitive neuroscience perspective 19<br />

<strong>The</strong> direction in which to head in order to construct artificial systems<br />

that are resilient to this kind of breakdown and that can tell us something<br />

new about emotion itself is to go beyond <strong>the</strong> simulation of mere external<br />

behavior and to pay attention to <strong>the</strong> mechanisms that generate such behavior<br />

in real organisms. <strong>Robot</strong>ics has in fact recently taken such a route, in large<br />

part due to <strong>the</strong> realization that its neglect results in systems whose behavior<br />

is just too rigid and breaks down in unanticipated cases. <strong>The</strong> next steps, I<br />

believe, are to look at feelings, <strong>the</strong>n at emotions, and finally <strong>the</strong> social behavior<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y help regulate. Roughly, if you build in <strong>the</strong> feelings, <strong>the</strong><br />

emotions and <strong>the</strong> social behavior follow more easily.<br />

<strong>The</strong> evidence that social communication draws upon feeling comes from<br />

various avenues. Important recent findings are related to simulation, as reviewed<br />

at length in Chapter 6 (Jeannerod). Data ranging from neurophysiological<br />

studies in monkeys (Gallese & Goldman, 1999) to lesion studies in<br />

humans (Adolphs, 2002) support <strong>the</strong> idea that we figure out how o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

people feel, in part, by simulating aspects of <strong>the</strong>ir presumed body state and<br />

that such a mechanism plays a key role in how we communicate socially.<br />

Such a mechanism would simulate in <strong>the</strong> observer <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> person<br />

observed by estimating <strong>the</strong> motor representations that gave rise to <strong>the</strong> behavior.<br />

Once we have generated <strong>the</strong> state that we presume <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r person<br />

to share, a representation of this actual state in ourselves could trigger conceptual<br />

knowledge. Of course, this is not <strong>the</strong> only mechanism whereby we<br />

obtain information about <strong>the</strong> mental states of o<strong>the</strong>rs; inference-based reasoning<br />

strategies and a collection of abilities dubbed “<strong>the</strong>ory of mind” participate<br />

in this process as well.<br />

<strong>The</strong> simulation hypo<strong>the</strong>sis has recently received considerable attention<br />

due to experimental findings that appear to support it. In <strong>the</strong> premotor<br />

cortex of monkeys, neurons that respond not only when <strong>the</strong> monkey prepares<br />

to perform an action itself but also when it observes <strong>the</strong> same visually<br />

presented action performed by ano<strong>the</strong>r have been reported (Gallese,<br />

Fadiga, Fogassi, & Rizzolatti, 1996; Gallese & Goldman, 1999; Rizzolatti,<br />

Fadiga, Gallese, & Fogassi, 1996). Various supportive findings have also<br />

been obtained in humans: observing ano<strong>the</strong>r’s actions results in desynchronization<br />

in motor cortex as measured with magnetoencephalography<br />

(Hari et al., 1998) and lowers <strong>the</strong> threshold for producing motor responses<br />

when transcranial magnetic stimulation is used to activate motor cortex<br />

(Strafella & Paus, 2000); imitating ano<strong>the</strong>r’s actions via observation activates<br />

premotor cortex in functional imaging studies (Iacoboni et al., 1999);<br />

moreover, such activation is somatotopic with respect to <strong>the</strong> body part that<br />

is observed to perform <strong>the</strong> action, even in <strong>the</strong> absence of any overt action<br />

on <strong>the</strong> part of <strong>the</strong> subject (Buccino et al., 2001). It thus appears that primates<br />

construct motor representations suited to performing <strong>the</strong> same action

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!