09.10.2013 Views

Witti-Buch2 2001.qxd - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Witti-Buch2 2001.qxd - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Witti-Buch2 2001.qxd - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Leszek Pyra<br />

And it is just here that J.Baird Callicot comes to the rescue. Generally he tries to<br />

articulate, defend and develop the ideas of Leopold, and is interested in such elaboration<br />

of Leopold's ethic which results, ethically and metaphysically, in producing a new<br />

paradigm, the ecocentric paradigm, remaining in contrast to the so far existing<br />

psychocentric or homocentric paradigms. Callicot admits that one of the main<br />

weaknesses of Leopold's legacy was the author's naive presumption that it was easy to<br />

shift from is to ought. He writes: "Leopold has blithely stepped across the barrier<br />

separating is from ought, that is, he has commited the naturalistic fallacy...". /Callicot,<br />

117/ The author searches for the new solution of this traditional problem and therefore<br />

he reaches to David Hume's theory of moral sense introduced in A Treatise of Human<br />

Nature /Hume ,469/, and to the theory of feelings presented by Charles Darwin in his<br />

The Descent of Man /Darwin, 107/. From the philogenetical point of view it seems that<br />

feelings are much older than reason - on the one hand, and that they are common in<br />

organisms other than human - on the other. As such they constitute a good basis for<br />

building a shift from facts to values, referring not to any kind of formal logic - where the<br />

problem seems to get no good solution at all - but to psychology. In this context Callicot<br />

pays particular attention to Hume's opinion that morality was not the question of reason<br />

but of feelings, of certain moral sentiments - natural and universal - in which everyone<br />

was endowed /Hume, 469-70/. But eventually Callicot too easily, I think, makes little<br />

account of the problem under discussion writing: "The naturalistic fallacy is dismissed as<br />

an issue too parochial to be practically relevant to contemporary environmental ethics."<br />

/Callicot, 118/. The reasonings sketched above point to the conclusion that from the<br />

knowledge of facts there do not follow any moral obligations conceived in any strictly<br />

logical sense. But one should accept such a theoretical position in which the knowledge<br />

of facts constitutes the psychological reason for obligations. It simply means that<br />

empirical biological knowledge makes us take care of the environment which eventually<br />

conditiones our well-being.<br />

Callicot claims that his axiology is humanly grounded but not humanly centered. He<br />

claims that holistic ethic wants to overcome the limitations of traditional ethical theories<br />

which attribute values only to individuals /primo loco: humans/, and wants to attribute<br />

values to biotopic communities /wholes/. Therefore it seems, I think, that the more<br />

holistic ethic is the more attention it pays to some greater wholes and the less to<br />

individuals. But it certainly cannot be totally holistic, because then it would attribute<br />

almost no value to individuals.<br />

The author radically distinguishes wild animals from domesticated ones. According<br />

to him the latter are simply some kind of artifacts, therefore it is nonsense to speak even<br />

about granting freedom to them, as animal liberation movement suggests /Callicot, 30-1/.<br />

If people set free domesticated animals, e.g. feral cattle and sheep, such animals would<br />

204

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!