09.10.2013 Views

Witti-Buch2 2001.qxd - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Witti-Buch2 2001.qxd - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Witti-Buch2 2001.qxd - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Incoherence of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s (Weak)<br />

Idealism<br />

Lambert Vincent Stepanich<br />

I<br />

At the heart of Kant's idealism is the idea that the human subject constitutes its own<br />

experience. This of course is his famous reversal: where once it was assumed that our<br />

cognition must conform to its objects we shall now suppose, and with greater success,<br />

that these objects must conform to our cognition (1996, Bxvi). The same direction of<br />

determination is evident in the later <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s account of the relation between<br />

human activity and an understanding of the world, and is the reason for ascribing to him<br />

a type of Kantian idealism. "Grammar is not accountable to any reality," <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

famously remarks, for the rules of grammar themselves constitute meaning (1974a, §<br />

184). It is the structure of our language, therefore, that "tells what kind of object anything<br />

is" (1958, § 373). When we observe what something is we are merely noting our own<br />

convention (1978, Pt. I, § 73). For this reason <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> speaks of "Theology as<br />

grammar," and he is careful to add: "The great difficulty here is not to represent the<br />

matter as if there were something one couldn't do. As if there really were an object, from<br />

which I derive its description, but I were unable to shew it to anyone" (1958, § 374).<br />

What underlies this grammar is nothing but the ways in which we use words, the<br />

various "games" we play with language. Human activity therefore grounds meaning, or<br />

the structure of a language, and so also the significance objects have for us (1969, §<br />

204). Yet this activity is itself ungrounded; it is simply there, "like our life"-"[w]hat has to<br />

be accepted, the given" (1969, § 559, and 1958, Pt. II, xi, 226). On account of being<br />

ungrounded, the language-games constituted by our practices are also arbitrary. Our<br />

practices are one way but they might have been another-and so too, therefore, might<br />

have the essence of objects. There are other ways in which we may have divided up<br />

the world (1981, § 331). Here no doubt we find a dissimilarity with Kant's idealism.<br />

The idea that human beings constitute their own experience can be developed in<br />

two ways, however, which parallel Kant's analysis in the Analytic and the Aesthetic and<br />

which we may speak of as "weak idealism" and "strong idealism" respectively. Weak<br />

idealism is the position that what we take objects to be is established by us, and that we<br />

cannot encounter objects but through our interpretations of them. It is idealism as<br />

318

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!