02.05.2013 Views

Evolution__3rd_Edition

Evolution__3rd_Edition

Evolution__3rd_Edition

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

..<br />

homozygotes by normal Mendelian segregation in the next<br />

generation. For one locus, heterozygote advantage is plausible.<br />

A few individuals die because they are homozygotes, but the<br />

population continues to exist.<br />

However, initial surveys suggested that about 3,000 loci might<br />

be polymorphic in fruitflies. Suppose all 3,000 were maintained by<br />

heterozygous advantage. The chance that an individual would be<br />

heterozygous at all 3,000 is essentially zero. All individuals will be<br />

homozygous at many hundreds of loci. If each such locus lowers<br />

fitness by a few percent, every individual will be dead several<br />

times over. (In terms of the example of sickle cell anemia, it is as if<br />

everyone has some such condition at hundreds of their loci. You<br />

might survive one of them, but not all of them.) Kimura concluded<br />

that it was impossible for natural selection to maintain all the<br />

genetic variation observed at the molecular level. The genetic<br />

variation must be maintained by random drift, which explains<br />

polymorphism by a balance of drift and mutation (Section 6.6,<br />

p. 150). Neutral variation does not create a genetic load.<br />

Kimura’s argument retains its interest, but is now generally<br />

thought to be inconclusive, for two main reasons. One is that the<br />

upper limits on the rate of evolution, and on the tolerable level of<br />

genetic variation, can be raised if we allow for soft selection.<br />

Haldane and Kimura’s calculation assumed hard selection. Hard<br />

selection means that natural selection adds to the amount of<br />

mortality, decreasing the population size. We can distinguish<br />

between “background” mortality, due to normal ecological<br />

processes (Section 4.1, p. 72), and “selective” mortality, due to<br />

the action of natural selection. Organisms produce many more<br />

offspring than can survive, and many die without reproducing.<br />

If a cod produces 5,000,000 eggs, on average 4,999,998 die<br />

before reproducing, because of the operation of various ecological<br />

mortality factors. Natural selection is hard if it reduces the number<br />

of survivors below two. Natural selection is soft if converts some<br />

of the background ecological mortality into selective mortality.<br />

Population size is not reduced if selection is soft.<br />

As a concrete example, imagine the population size is limited by<br />

the number of breeding territories. Only 100 territories exist in an<br />

area, and non-owners soon die of starvation. The 100 territory<br />

owners produce 10 eggs each, making 1,000 eggs in all. Half the<br />

eggs die before growing up into adults, such that 500 adults<br />

compete for the 100 territories each generation (400 will fail a<br />

though the numbers might need adjusting if gender introduces<br />

complexities). Consider first extreme soft selection. A new<br />

advantageous genotype arises, which increases juvenile survival,<br />

perhaps by 20%. Once the genotype is fixed, 600 juveniles will<br />

survive to become adults. However, the same 100 territories exist<br />

and the reproductive output of the population will not be altered.<br />

Compare that with hard selection. A new disease arises that is<br />

only caught by territory holders. A new genotype arises, making<br />

CHAPTER 7 / Natural Selection and Random Drift 163<br />

the birds resistant to the disease; most of the birds initially have a<br />

disease-susceptible genotype. Until the disease-resistant genotype<br />

is being substituted by natural selection, the reproductive output<br />

of the birds will decrease. The mortality caused by the disease is<br />

additional. It comes on top of the ecological winnowing down,<br />

caused by the limited supply of territories.<br />

Substitutional load ultimately limits the rate of evolution<br />

whether selection is hard or soft, but the limit is much lower with<br />

hard selection. Much selection in fact is probably soft, and does not<br />

reduce the reproductive output of a population. <strong>Evolution</strong> can then<br />

proceed at a higher rate than that calculated by Kimura and<br />

Haldane.<br />

The second counterargument is that natural selection can act<br />

jointly on many loci. In the argument above about heterozgous<br />

advantage, we assumed that each homozygous locus in an<br />

individual reduces fitness by a few percent. Natural selection may<br />

not work like that. An individual may be able to survive equally well<br />

with one, two, three, or 100 homozygous loci, and only after the<br />

number of homozygous loci goes over some threshold, such as 500,<br />

will that individual’s fitness seriously decrease. Then, many more<br />

heterozygous loci can be maintained in the population than if each<br />

locus contributes its own mortality. A similar argument can be made<br />

for the rate of evolution. A distinction is being made here between<br />

multiplicative fitnesses, in which each locus contributes its own<br />

independent effect on the organism’s fitness, and epistatic<br />

fitnesses, in which the effects of different loci are not independent.<br />

Section 8.8 (p. 206) looks at the distinction more. It also features in<br />

the arguments about sex in Section 12.2.2 (p. 323).<br />

A third counterargument is that genetic variation can be<br />

maintained by frequency-dependent selection without creating a<br />

genetic load. (The sex ratio, which maintains the X and Y<br />

chromosomes, is an example: see Section 12.5, p. 337.) Thus,<br />

even if Kimura’s argument rules out heterozygous advantage<br />

as the explanation of much genetic variation, it does not rule<br />

out all forms of natural selection.<br />

These counterarguments have not been shown to be correct in<br />

fact. They are hypothetical arguments, and reduce the theoretical<br />

force of Kimura’s case. Neutral theory, for this reason, is now<br />

usually supported by arguments other than genetic load. However,<br />

the arguments are still worth knowing. They have been historically<br />

influential and also still constantly crop up, in one form or another,<br />

in many areas of evolutionary biology. Moreover, Williams (1992)<br />

suggested that the whole problem had been swept under the rug<br />

rather than solved, and that biologists should be paying more<br />

attention to the problem of loads.<br />

Further reading: Lewontin (1974), Kimura (1983), Williams (1992),<br />

Gillespie (1998).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!