02.05.2013 Views

Evolution__3rd_Edition

Evolution__3rd_Edition

Evolution__3rd_Edition

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

..<br />

*<br />

*<br />

The word “gene” is being used in a<br />

technical sense<br />

Criticisms have been made<br />

B<br />

b<br />

b'<br />

b"<br />

*<br />

*<br />

CHAPTER 11 / The Units of Selection 309<br />

Figure 11.4<br />

When intragenic recombination happens between two alleles with<br />

different heterozygous nucleotides, it breaks the gene structure.<br />

The * indicates where the nucleotide sequence differs from the<br />

allele. The gene sequences coming out of recombination differ<br />

from the initial sequences.<br />

p. 210) and builds up linkage disequilibrium between genes. The same will be true of<br />

loci further down the DNA from the selected locus. The hitch-hiking effect is gradually<br />

reduced with distance by recombination, but there is no clear cut-off. This poses<br />

no problem for Williams’ definition of the gene. The neighboring allele that is hitchhiking<br />

with the selected mutation is, in Williams’ definition, part of the gene that is<br />

having its frequency altered.<br />

Williams’ “gene” has a statistical reality, because shorter lengths of DNA are more<br />

permanent and longer lengths are less permanent. The random hits of recombination<br />

will generate a frequency distribution of genome lengths lasting for different periods of<br />

evolutionary time. The average length that survives long enough for natural selection to<br />

work on has been defined by Williams and Dawkins as the gene. Population geneticists<br />

have scolded them from time to time for assuming a one-locus, zero linkage disequilibrium<br />

view of evolution, but the dispute is a matter of definition, not substance. The<br />

critics are identifying “gene” with “cistron.” It would be interesting to know whether<br />

the gene in Williams’ sense is also a physical cistron; but it is a secondary question and<br />

has nothing to do with the fundamental logic of Williams and Dawkins’ argument.<br />

We must discuss one further matter before considering the significance of the genic<br />

unit of selection. Critics, such as Gould (2002b), have objected that gene frequencies<br />

change between generations only in a passive, “book-keeping” sense. The frequency<br />

changes provide a record of evolution, but are not its fundamental cause. True natural<br />

selection, the critics would say, happens at the level of organismic survival and reproduction.<br />

The actual selection in the lion example happens when a lion catches, or fails<br />

to catch, its prey. The differential hunting success drives the gene frequency changes,<br />

and it is a mistake to identify the gene frequency changes as causal. Williams and<br />

Dawkins, however, do not deny that whatever ecological processes are causing differential<br />

organismic survival produce gene frequency changes within a generation. What<br />

they deny is that this ecological interaction of organisms means that natural selection<br />

directly adjusts the frequencies of organisms over the evolutionary timescale of many<br />

generations.<br />

There is an easy philosophical method of deciding whether natural selection<br />

works on genes or larger phenotypic units. We can consider a phenotypic change<br />

such as a new hunting skill, and ask whether natural selection can work on it if it is produced<br />

genically and if it is produced non-genically. The case we discussed above was<br />

genic: the advantageous new hunting behavior was caused by a genetic mutation. Now<br />

suppose that the same advantageous phenotypic change was caused by a non-heritable

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!