13.07.2015 Views

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

136Chapter 4embodied in a visibly identifiable gathering of au<strong>to</strong>nomous citizens.It pulls back in<strong>to</strong> the, as it were, "subjectless" forms ofcommunication circulating through forums <strong>and</strong> legislative bodies.Only in this anonymous form can its communicatively fluid powerbind the administrative power of the state apparatus <strong>to</strong> the will ofthe citizens. As we will see, in the democratic rule of law, politicalpower is differentiated in<strong>to</strong> communicative power <strong>and</strong> administrativepower. Because popular sovereignty no longer concentrates ina collectivity, or in the physically tangible presence of the unitedcitizens or their assembled representatives, but only takes effect inthe circulation of reasonably structured deliberations <strong>and</strong> decisions,one can attribute a harmless meaning <strong>to</strong> the proposition thatthere cannot be a sovereign in the constitutional state.2 But thisinterpretation must be carefully defined so as not <strong>to</strong> divest popularsovereignty of its radical-democratic content.When, in the folJowing, we reconstruct the internal relationbetween law <strong>and</strong> political power, we must be careful from the start<strong>to</strong> avoid a misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing. This investigation is not concernedwith the gap between norm <strong>and</strong> reality, <strong>and</strong> thus does not yetapproach power as a socialfacticity able <strong>to</strong> make ideas look foolish.As in the previous chapter, our attention is directed rather at the.tension between facticity <strong>and</strong> validity inside the law. This initiallyappeared in the dimension oflegal validity (as the tension betweenthe positivity <strong>and</strong> the legitimacy of law) <strong>and</strong> inside the system ofrights (as the tension between private <strong>and</strong> public au<strong>to</strong>nomy).These perspectives broaden when we introduce the idea of theconstitutional state. From rights we move over <strong>to</strong> a constitutionallyorganized authority whose exercise is supposed <strong>to</strong> be bound <strong>to</strong>legitima:te law. Once law is reflexively applied <strong>to</strong> the political powerit tacitly presupposes, of course, the tension between facticity <strong>and</strong>validity shifts <strong>to</strong> another dimension: it reappears in constitutionallyorganized political power itself. State power is based on a threat ofsanctions backed by instruments of force held in reserve; at thesame time, however, it is authorized by legitimate law. As is the casein legal validity, the two moments of coercion <strong>and</strong> claim <strong>to</strong> normativevalidity are also combined in the collective binding force ofpolitical decisions, though in the opposite way. Whereas the lawinherently claims normative validity regardless of its positivity,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!