13.07.2015 Views

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

294Chapter 7competing parties. This public wants <strong>to</strong> be convinced that the oneparty offers the prospect of better policies than does the otherparty; there must be good reasons for preferring one party <strong>to</strong> theother. Here one finally reaches the point where something thatlooks plausible from the observer perspective can no longer betranslated in<strong>to</strong> an argument that looks plausible <strong>to</strong> participants inthe same way. The attempt at such a translation leads, underempiricist premises, <strong>to</strong> contradictions.(d) From the objectivating viewpoint of the empiricist model, thestruggle of parties for political power lacks a validity dimension.Becker does not cease <strong>to</strong> reiterate the point that political argumentsare exhausted by their rhe<strong>to</strong>rical functions. Political argumentsare intended not <strong>to</strong> be rationally acceptable but <strong>to</strong> beperlocutionarily effective: "In democracy it is not a question ofascertaining the 'objective truth' of political policies. It is rather amatter of establishing conditions for the democratic acceptabilityof the goals that the parties pursue. To this extent, the function ofpolitical arguments is . .. more that of advertising, or 'weapons' thatcircumvent the use of physical force, than that of assertions onecould interpret as providing support for 'true' theories."7 Thenormatively laden but vague terms of political debate have ratheran emotional significance: they are intended <strong>to</strong> create mass commitments.Accordingly, political speech has "a social-psychological,not a cognitive, function."8Becker must explain why citizens, <strong>and</strong> not just the elites, seethrough the emotional meaning of pseudoargumentative advertising-<strong>and</strong>nonetheless accept it. It is assumed that the empiricistself-description does not have deleterious effects on their motivation<strong>to</strong> participate, because enlightened citizens already have a nononsenseview of the political process as compromise formation.But even compromises must be grounded, <strong>and</strong> what grounds theacceptance of compromises? On the one h<strong>and</strong>, there are nonormative st<strong>and</strong>ards by which the fairness of compromises couldbe assessed. Social justice, for instance, is relegated <strong>to</strong> the sphere ofpublic-relations rhe<strong>to</strong>ric: "In the political reality of liberal democraciesthis [i.e., social justice] is a systematically superfluous idea."On the other h<strong>and</strong>, participants should still have good reasons forentering in<strong>to</strong> compromises: "Under the conditions of a competi-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!