13.07.2015 Views

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

541Notes <strong>to</strong> pages 225-23154. A. J. Arnaud, R. Hilpinen, <strong>and</strong> J. Wroblewski, eds., Juristische Logik undIrrationalitiit im Recht, Rechtstheorie Beiheft 8 ( 1985).55. Toulmin, Uses of Argument; Toulmin, Rieke, <strong>and</strong> Janik, Introduction <strong>to</strong> Reasoning.56. K. 0. Ape!, Charles S. Peirce, trans.]. M. Krois (Amherst, Mass., 1981); see alsoK. 0. Ape!, "Sprache und Bedeutung, Wahrheit und normative Gultigkeit,"Archivo di Filosophia 55 (1987): 51-88.57. See my excursus on argumentation theory in TCA, 1:22-42.58. Aulis Aarnio begins by conceiving legitimacy, one of the two dimensions oflegal validity, as rational acceptability (The Rational as Reasonable [Bos<strong>to</strong>n, 1987],pp. 43ff.). He goes on <strong>to</strong> discuss various sorts of legal norms, arranging thesecategories of valid law hierarchically (pp. 6lff. <strong>and</strong> 78ff. ): these are the "sourcesofinformation." Aarnio then deals with the discourse rules that govern interpretation;these constitute the "sources of rationality." Like Dworkin, he mainlyemphasizes the externaljustification of the premises of decisions, which requires .substantial reasons, <strong>to</strong> wit, principles <strong>and</strong> policies (rightness reasons vs. goalreasons). Unlike Dworkin, however, <strong>to</strong> justify these principles Aarnio does notrequire the construction of an encompassing theory but only coherence underthe conditions of rational discourse:[T]he justification procedure is essentially a dialogue. It is a succession ofquestions <strong>and</strong> answers on the basis of which different pro <strong>and</strong> contra argumentswill be presented . ... The addressee can rationally accept the interpretation onlyif the justification results in a coherent cluster of statements <strong>and</strong> if this clusterfulfills [certain] criteria [above all criteria for the connection <strong>to</strong> valid law] . ...This is so, because the st<strong>and</strong>ards oflegal reasoning alone do not guarantee thecoherence of the justifica<strong>to</strong>ry material. All reasons must also be used in a rationalway. (Aarnio, p. 187)Good reasons display their rationally motivating force only in a forum thatgrants a hearing <strong>to</strong> all relevant voices. Aarnio describes this forum in terms ofChaim Perelman's concept of the "ideal audience." Naturally, for legal discoursea particular ideal audience limited <strong>to</strong> the boundaries of the legal communitysuffices. This audience consists of rational persons who allow the unforced forceof the better argument <strong>to</strong> determine whether they take a yes or no positionthoughonly within the context of a concrete form of life they already share.59. R. Alexy, A Theory of Legal Argumentation, trans. R. Adler <strong>and</strong> N. MacCormick(Oxford, 1989); Alexy, Theorie derjuristischenArgumentation, 2d ed. (Frankfurt amMain, 1991); Alexy refers <strong>to</strong> J. Habermas, "Wahrheitstheorien," which is availablein Habermas, Vorstudien und Ergiinzungen zur Theorie des kommunikativenH<strong>and</strong>elns (Frankfurt am Main, 1984) , pp. 127-83.60. J. Habermas, "Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of PhilosophicalJustification," in Moral Consciousness <strong>and</strong> Communicative Action, trans. C. Lenhardt<strong>and</strong> S. W. Nicholsen (Cambridge, Mass., 1990), pp. 43-1 15.61. In his afterword, Alexy indeed distinguishes the rationality of established law

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!