13.07.2015 Views

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

202Chapter 5out the internal normative character of legal rules <strong>and</strong> the systematicconstruction of a system of rules. This system is supposed <strong>to</strong>facilitate the consistency of rule-bound decisions <strong>and</strong> render thelaw largely independent of politics. In contrast <strong>to</strong> hermeneuticists,positivists emphasize the closed character <strong>and</strong> au<strong>to</strong>nomy of a legalsystem impermeable <strong>to</strong> extralegal principles. Thus the rationalityproblem is resolved in a way that gives priority <strong>to</strong> a narrowlyconceived institutional his<strong>to</strong>ry purged of any suprapositive validitybasis. A "basic norm" or "rule of recognition" enables one <strong>to</strong>determine unambiguously which norms belong <strong>to</strong> valid law (geltendenRecht) at a given point in time.An au<strong>to</strong>nomous legal system of this sort is differentiated in<strong>to</strong>primary rules for regulating behavior <strong>and</strong> secondary rules for theself-referential production of norms. If we presuppose that law isau<strong>to</strong>nomous in this way, then the validity of legal regulations ismeasured solely by the observance oflegally stipulated proceduresoflawmaking. This legitimation through the legality of the lawmakingprocedure privileges the pedigree-namely, the correct processof enactment-over the rational justification of a norm'scontent: rules are valid because they are properly enacted by thecompetent institutions. The legitimation of the legal order as awhole shifts <strong>to</strong> its origin, that is, <strong>to</strong> a basic norm or rule ofrecognition that legitimates everythingwithou t itselfbeing capableof rational justification; as part of a his<strong>to</strong>rical form oflife , it must befactually accepted as settled cus<strong>to</strong>m. Hart makes this plausible bydrawing on Wittgenstein's concept of a language game. Like thegrammar of a language game, the rule of recognition is rooted ina practice that, though described externally as a fact, is taken by theparticipants themselves as self-evidently valid.12Tying the validity oflaw <strong>to</strong> its genesis allows only an asymmetricalsolution <strong>to</strong> the rationality problem. Reason or justice is <strong>to</strong> a certainextent subordinated <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ry. Hence the positivist reading ofjudicial decision making privileges the certainty guarantee at theexpense of the rightness guarantee. The priority of legal certaintyis evident in the positivist treatment of "hard cases." In these cases,the hermeneutical problem becomes especially clear: how can theappropriateness of unavoidably selective decisions be justified?Positivism plays down this problem, analyzing its effects as symp-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!