13.07.2015 Views

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

Between Facts and Norms - Contributions to a ... - Blogs Unpad

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

44Chapter 2<strong>and</strong> john Millar, still st<strong>and</strong>ing between classical politics <strong>and</strong> contemporarypolitical economy, were just beginning the move fromAris<strong>to</strong>tle <strong>to</strong> Marx.2 As empiricists, they opposed the prescriptivismofa rational law whose normative arguments disregarded his<strong>to</strong>ricalparticularity <strong>and</strong> sociocultural facts. As early sociologists <strong>and</strong> anthropologists,they opposed a rationalism that would neatly resolvethe informal fabric of received social relations, established institutions,deeply anchored interest positions, <strong>and</strong> class structures in adeliberately constructed system of rules.To be sure, the model of the social contract found support in theevidence that modern exchange society seemed <strong>to</strong> secure somethinglike a natural au<strong>to</strong>nomy <strong>and</strong> equality for private personsthrough their participation in market transactions. With its spontaneoustendency <strong>to</strong> guarantee freedom, the only thing bourgeoiseconomic society (or civil society, burgerlichen Gesellschaft) stillseemed <strong>to</strong> lack was establishment in formal legal terms. True, thisintuition was explicated only in the liberal versions found in johnLocke through Immanuel Kant <strong>and</strong> Thomas Paine.3 But in allsocial-contract theories, the intention of constructing basic institutionsalong the lines of rational natural law amounted <strong>to</strong> the viewthat society as a whole could be unders<strong>to</strong>od as the intentional. complex of a free association of originally au<strong>to</strong>nomous <strong>and</strong> equalmembers.4 This improbable idea gained a certain plausibility onlybecause modern market societies initially appeared as a naturalbasis on which parties encounter one another as inherently free<strong>and</strong> equal. Why "inherently"? Under the egalitarian conditions ofan equilibrated, small-scale, commodity economy (as Marx will callit), commodity owners-who were imagined as male heads ofhousehold-already seemed virtually <strong>to</strong> occupy the position ofprivately au<strong>to</strong>nomous subjects of law, prior <strong>to</strong> all intentionallyproduced political association. Certainly this background was lessimportant in those authors who characterized the state of naturenot in terms of economic relations but of power. Still, Hobbesianconstructions of the state of nature were at least equivalent <strong>to</strong> thesupposition that bourgeois society functioned, prior <strong>to</strong> all legalregulation, as the source of political association. It could serve thisfunction because competitive economic relations already requiresubjects who conclude contracts <strong>and</strong> <strong>to</strong> this extent make law.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!