12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

114 J.J. <strong>Haldane</strong><br />

To bring this out consider a further ambiguity. What is meant by<br />

talking about ‘many universes’? In futuristic fantasies, space travellers often<br />

journey to ‘other worlds’. This way of speaking of far away <strong>and</strong> hitherto<br />

unknown places pre-dates science fiction. The European explorers of the<br />

fifteenth <strong>and</strong> sixteenth centuries sailed from the ‘old’ world <strong>and</strong> discovered<br />

the ‘new’, but in saying so no one intends that they left the planet. Similarly<br />

one might speak of ‘other universes’ meaning far distant <strong>and</strong> currently<br />

unobservable regions of the Universe – the one spatio-temporal-causal<br />

continuum. Alternatively one might mean, though this is much harder to<br />

make sense of, entirely distinct cosmic set-ups, wholly discontinuous with<br />

the Universe we inhabit.<br />

If the hypothesis of plural universes invokes the former idea then it is clear<br />

enough what is being said, but it should also be evident that it fails to serve<br />

the purpose intended. Any evidence we could have for the existence of<br />

spatially or temporally distant regions <strong>and</strong> systems would necessarily be evidence<br />

for situations generally like those obtaining in our sector – that is to say<br />

situations exhibiting the same finely tuned features whose existence seemed<br />

to call for explanation. This is so because all that could lead us to postulate<br />

<strong>and</strong> predict the character of distant universes would be the application<br />

of observational-cum-inferential methods to empirical-cum-theoretical data<br />

available to us here. So if ‘many universes’ means ‘many local set-ups’ within<br />

the Universe the hypothesis fails to defuse the power of the new design<br />

argument. If on the other h<strong>and</strong> it is being claimed that there could be many<br />

Universes – entirely distinct realities, wholly discontinuous <strong>and</strong> sharing no<br />

common elements – then, while it is uncertain how to interpret this, it is clear<br />

that there could be no empirical evidence in support of the hypothesis, <strong>and</strong><br />

nor could it be derived as a necessary condition of the possible existence<br />

<strong>and</strong> character of the only universe of which we have or could have scientific<br />

knowledge. In short the hypothesis appears as entirely ad hoc, introduced only<br />

to avoid what for the naturalist is an unpalatable conclusion, viz., that the<br />

general regularities <strong>and</strong> particular fine tuning are due to the agency of a<br />

designer – et hoc dicimus Deum.<br />

Some readers will be struck by the parallels between the many universes<br />

hypothesis <strong>and</strong> another theoretical construction, namely the so-called ‘Many-<br />

Worlds Interpretation’ of quantum mechanics. This is a response to a deeply<br />

puzzling feature of a major part of fundamental physics. In a quantummechanical<br />

situation it seems that there are indeterministic transitions<br />

between states. The theory tells us that a system will go from A to either B or<br />

C, but in principle it cannot tell us which one it will go to – the outcome is<br />

indeterminate. Among those who find this situation unacceptable some maintain<br />

that the uncertainty is only epistemological. There is a fact of the matter<br />

involving ‘hidden variables’ but for one reason or another we do not, or

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!