12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

236 J.J. <strong>Haldane</strong><br />

the thought or perception of a cat say, there are two aspects: nature (the conceptual<br />

or perceptual content), <strong>and</strong> the fact of its being actualized in the<br />

thought. An intentional content does not imply the existence of a cognition<br />

in which it is tokened, <strong>and</strong> so the actual occurrence of a thought calls for an<br />

explanation in terms of some efficient cause of it. Here the anti-realist’s<br />

journey to God may be shorter than that of the realist since it skips out a<br />

chain of interacting natural substances <strong>and</strong> moves directly to mind as the<br />

cause of ideas, <strong>and</strong> thence from contingently to necessarily existing mind.<br />

Such is one way in which anti-realism may be linked to theism. This,<br />

however, does not rely on any feature distinctive of anti-realism, but only<br />

on showing that the anti-realist has to allow instances of that from which<br />

the realist argument also starts, i.e. existent being. Next I wish to examine<br />

a different link: one which proceeds from a claim that the realist certainly<br />

denies, namely that the world is constituted by the ways in which we do, or in<br />

which we could, conceive or experience it. The most immediate route to this<br />

anti-realist theses is that laid out by Berkeley in his Treatise Concerning Principles<br />

of Human Knowledge, when he argues that the common assumption that<br />

the objects we perceive exist independently of their being perceived involves<br />

a contradiction. Berkeley writes:<br />

what are [houses, mountains, rivers] but the things that we perceive by sense,<br />

<strong>and</strong> what do we perceive besides our own ideas or sensations; <strong>and</strong> is it not<br />

plainly repugnant that any one of these or any combination of them should<br />

exist unperceived? . . . all the choir of heaven <strong>and</strong> furniture of the earth, in a<br />

word all those bodies which compose the mighty frame of the world, have not<br />

any subsistence without a mind, their being is to be perceived or known. 14<br />

In reply, the realist will protest that one can think of many things existing<br />

unperceived or unconceived – such as objects far away in space <strong>and</strong> time. But<br />

Berkeley is ready with his response, namely that just as one cannot see a thing<br />

that is at the same time unseen, so it makes no sense to claim to conceive a<br />

thing which is unconceived; <strong>and</strong> since what is conceived exists as such in the<br />

mind, so in conceiving of something ‘unconceived’ one is not in fact conceiving<br />

of something outside the mind itself. 15<br />

One may respond to Berkeley’s overall argument by drawing on two distinctions,<br />

each of which serves to disambiguate innocent <strong>and</strong> threatening<br />

interpretations of such claims as that thought involves ideas, <strong>and</strong> that what is<br />

conceived is ipso facto in the mind of a thinker. The first is between ideas or<br />

concepts as media, <strong>and</strong> as objects of thought. In the Summa Theologiae Aquinas<br />

writes that ‘ideas st<strong>and</strong> in relation to the intellect as that by which the intellect<br />

thinks <strong>and</strong> not as what is thought of ’. 16 Secondly, it is one thing to be<br />

spatially present or contiguous <strong>and</strong> another to be cognitively so. Conjoining

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!