12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

246 J.J. <strong>Haldane</strong><br />

but which will not be made the better for being elaborated at length. I do not<br />

assume that we can tell what sorts of goods justify these evils, or see how they<br />

might do so in particular cases. I do assume, though, that they have a natural<br />

or supernatural justification. In saying this, however, I think we must be<br />

willing to contemplate the possibility that the occurrence of some evils is, in<br />

a sense, necessarily arbitrary. Consider an economic analogy. Suppose it is<br />

logically the case that certain ranges of high benefit economies require patterns<br />

of innovation in production <strong>and</strong> use that mean that at any given time<br />

a certain percentage of the population is unemployed or otherwise suffering.<br />

It will then be true that very good economies involve temporary suffering.<br />

Together with certain empirical facts, this will be a sufficient explanation of<br />

why some particular individuals suffer as <strong>and</strong> when they do. Even so, the<br />

structural feature does not necessitate that it be these individuals who suffer.<br />

A victim or his representative may reasonably say that the overall good did<br />

not require that he or she be among the suffering, but it remains the case that<br />

some needed to suffer in order for the good to be realized. Perhaps matters<br />

could have been arranged so that the identities of those affected were different,<br />

but it could not have been arranged so that no-one suffered. Thus, while<br />

the actual occurrence of suffering was arbitrary, the fact that there was suffering<br />

was logically unavoidable.<br />

If that is how it is in the world more generally, then evil is justified even if<br />

its distribution is to some extent arbitrary, so that the innocent suffer. What<br />

need to be added are, first, the assumption that such a world is on balance a<br />

greater good than one from which such arbitrarily occurrent evils are absent;<br />

<strong>and</strong>, second, the supposition that God will somehow ‘take account’ of the misfortune<br />

of these victims (<strong>and</strong> of the perpetrators of great moral evils). I think<br />

these considerations point towards the Christian economy of salvation <strong>and</strong> to<br />

the four last things: death, judgement, heaven <strong>and</strong> hell. Addressing myself to<br />

the analytically <strong>and</strong> dialectically minded I have given little attention to experiential<br />

factors, but I do not at all regard them as unimportant <strong>and</strong> I choose<br />

to end with an appeal to a common phenomenon, that of religious desire.<br />

There is a style of argument, much ridiculed by its critics, which runs as<br />

follows:<br />

(1) Human beings have a natural desire for eternal life in the company<br />

of God.<br />

(2) Wherever there is a natural desire for something that thing must exist<br />

(or else the desire would be frustrated).<br />

(3) Therefore God exists.<br />

Assuming that the expression ‘the company of God’ is read extensionally,<br />

so that its correct application would imply the existence of its object, <strong>and</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!