12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

154 J.J.C. Smart<br />

a definite way. We can explain the behaviour of the receiver by physics<br />

together with a wiring diagram. Thus in the sense in which we might think<br />

of electronics (or part of it) as physics plus wiring diagrams, so the biochemical<br />

core of biology can be thought of as physics <strong>and</strong> chemistry plus natural<br />

history. 6 Of course the natural history needn’t be about tigers or gum trees:<br />

investigating the small structures seen by means of electron microscopes counts<br />

for me as natural history. In natural history we have mere generalizations, to<br />

which exceptions are the norm, hardly requiring explanation, <strong>and</strong> relating<br />

to things on planet earth, <strong>and</strong> so cosmically parochial. Thus consider a<br />

biochemical investigation of the functioning of a liver. ‘Liver’ is understood<br />

partly ostensively <strong>and</strong> partly in terms of what it usually does, what it has been<br />

selected for. 7<br />

One can therefore be an ontological physicalist without believing in emergence<br />

in any stronger sense than the weak sense that I have just elucidated. 8<br />

Nor need we be able to make detailed predictions from one level to the next<br />

to have good scientific <strong>and</strong> philosophical reasons to see the higher level as not<br />

only ontologically a matter of the lower level but as plausibly explained by it.<br />

Steven Weinberg puts the matter very persuasively in his Dreams of a Final<br />

Theory. 9 He argues as follows. The quantum theory of the chemical bond can<br />

be used in cases of simple atoms <strong>and</strong> molecules to explain the properties of<br />

the chemical bond, <strong>and</strong> even if this cannot be done in the case of very<br />

complicated molecules, this failure can be put down simply to the mathematical<br />

intractability of the problem. Because the nature of the chemical bond<br />

can be deduced from the quantum theory, this gives us a very good plausible<br />

reason for thinking that nature works in this way in mathematically intractable<br />

cases. We can still hold, as he says, that ‘there are no autonomous<br />

principles of chemistry that are simply independent truths, not resting on<br />

deeper principles of physics’. 10<br />

Having said that my reduction is ontological <strong>and</strong> not translational,<br />

I am not sure that I am using ‘ontological’ in quite the way in which <strong>Haldane</strong><br />

is (see p. 84). The weight of the average plumber is definable as the sum<br />

of the weights of plumbers divided by the number of plumbers. So talk of<br />

the average plumber is translatable into talk of the plumbers. However, I do<br />

not require translation for ontological reduction. I can still say that a tree is<br />

nothing over <strong>and</strong> above a physical mechanism, just as a radio receiver is, even<br />

though talk of a tree is not translatable into talk of electrons <strong>and</strong> protons.<br />

If non-translatability implied non-naturalism, non-naturalism would be too<br />

easily come by.<br />

I would also suggest that <strong>Haldane</strong>’s term ‘explanatory reductionism’ is<br />

not quite what I would mean by the term ‘reductionism’. Recall the matter of<br />

some chemical reaction. One could explain it by purely chemical considerations<br />

involving the chemical bonds of the molecules concerned. Nevertheless

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!