12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

244 J.J. <strong>Haldane</strong><br />

actual. Since any purported parallel will be an example of a created reality,<br />

which is precisely not simple, any analogy will be imperfect, but consider the<br />

cases of white light, ideal numbers, <strong>and</strong> intellectual ability. The first ‘contains’<br />

a plurality of colours, not realized as in a rainbow but existing virtually in<br />

a way that allows for their expression out of it. The number 28 both ‘contains’<br />

<strong>and</strong> is the sum of its factors (1, 2, 4, 7, 14), but they exist in it not as<br />

members of a set, though they can be extracted from it. When we say that<br />

someone was ‘full of ideas’ we mean he had an ability to conceive <strong>and</strong> formulate<br />

them, not that he contained them as a book contains sentences.<br />

In each case what come to be diverse in their expression pre-exist without<br />

actual difference in their source: from one reality come many effects. Likewise,<br />

the diversity of natures <strong>and</strong> existents are contained virtually <strong>and</strong> abstractly<br />

in God. Order in nature calls for an explanation which is provided by the<br />

hypothesis of a divine designer. It would be problematic if this meant that the<br />

designer’s mind had to exhibit the same order; but it does not. In general it is<br />

a fallacy to suppose that the number <strong>and</strong> diversity of effects has to be matched<br />

by a corresponding number <strong>and</strong> diversity of causes or aspects. Certainly what<br />

produces the effects must have the power to do so, <strong>and</strong> on that account it may<br />

be redescribed severally by reference to its products. On this account we may<br />

say that the effects (pre)exist eminently in the cause. It is quite compatible<br />

with this, however, that an intrinsic characterization of the cause should lack<br />

any differentiation of parts or aspects. Of course, natural causes are complex<br />

in respect of their actual structure <strong>and</strong> attributes, but from the theistic perspective<br />

they belong on the side of created effects. As ultimate cause, God<br />

cannot be complex, <strong>and</strong> nothing in the notions of efficient, formal, material<br />

or final causality per se, requires that he should be.<br />

7 God, Evil, <strong>and</strong> Hope<br />

In discussing the problem of evil I proceeded directly to offer a theodicy<br />

(a justifying explanation of its existence), not marking the usual distinction<br />

between this <strong>and</strong> a defence (the more limited task of showing that evil is<br />

compatible with the existence of God). I also failed both to separate explicitly<br />

the logical from the evidential forms of the problem, <strong>and</strong> to address the latter.<br />

In making good these omissions I shall be brief, both for reasons of space <strong>and</strong><br />

because I think that the deepest intellectual challenge posed by evil is theological<br />

rather than philosophical. It calls into question not the truth of theism,<br />

but the expectation that we might underst<strong>and</strong> the place of evil in the providential<br />

governance of the world. My seeing it in these terms is, of course,<br />

connected with my philosophical belief that there are good reasons to believe<br />

in God, <strong>and</strong> with my theological belief that God made us to know him.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!