12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Further Reflections on <strong>Atheism</strong> 209<br />

supernatural acquaintance with the Platonic entities, as is needed in traditional<br />

Platonism, going back to Plato himself.<br />

If one is not satisfied with the minimalist account of necessity, one might<br />

be tempted to define it in terms of possible worlds. There are two objections<br />

to this. One thing is that the notion of possible world is elucidated in terms<br />

of ‘the way things might be’ <strong>and</strong> ‘might’ is itself a form of ‘possibly’. Another<br />

is that if the possible worlds are ersatz, we may wonder what they have to do<br />

with the price of fish.<br />

If a theologian were a traditional Platonist as (opposed to a Quinean one),<br />

he or she might point to an unanalysed necessity apparently possessed by the<br />

square root of 2, e, π <strong>and</strong> so on. So, as I suggested in FE p. 37, the theologian<br />

might say that God is a necessary being in the way that the square root of 2<br />

is. Though if we give no clear meaning to the necessity ascribed to the square<br />

root of 2 we still have no clear meaning as to the necessity ascribed to God.<br />

Nevertheless as I suggested in FE, a theologian would do best to think of<br />

God as eternal, not sempiternal. (Anselm in Proslogion XIII says: ‘Only that<br />

in which there is neither beginning nor end nor conjunction of parts, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

thought does not discern save as a whole in every place <strong>and</strong> at every time,<br />

cannot be thought not to exist.’ This is ambiguous between being eternal, <strong>and</strong><br />

like the square root of 2 in not being in time or space–time at all, <strong>and</strong> being<br />

sempiternal, at all times, with time being infinite towards both past <strong>and</strong> future.)<br />

It is important to prise away the commonly confused notions of temporality<br />

<strong>and</strong> even sempiternity from that of existence. I think that even a traditional<br />

(non-Quinean) Platonist should feel the lure of the unanswerable<br />

question of ‘Why does anything exist at all?’ no less in relation to the atemporal<br />

forms than about things in space <strong>and</strong> time. The theist should feel it in<br />

relation to an atemporal God no less than in relation to a temporal God.<br />

Those who believe in a temporal God may also need to confront recent<br />

speculations in cosmology, such as that new space–time universes may be<br />

spawned out of black holes. Perhaps God is super-temporal with a very<br />

complicated branching topology. As I said in FE, my advice would be to<br />

think of God as atemporal, eternal not sempiternal. Even so, as I have suggested,<br />

this does not resolve the doubts about the nature of necessity, or fail<br />

to leave us with the child’s question ‘Who made God?’ (in the form of<br />

‘Is there a satisfactory sense of “necessary” which will get round a generalized<br />

form of J.N. Findlay’s challenge?’).<br />

6 The Fine-Tuning Argument Again<br />

Some reviewers have queried my treatment in FE of the fine-tuning arguments<br />

in which I surveyed various non-theistic ways of dealing with the fine-tuning

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!