12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Reply to Smart 175<br />

metaphysical answer involves acknowledging the existence of intensional entities<br />

– concepts <strong>and</strong> senses – which organize the realms of thought <strong>and</strong> meaning<br />

in a manner analogous to that in which natural forms organize the material<br />

world. The concept ‘cat’ st<strong>and</strong>s to a thought of a cat, as the form cat st<strong>and</strong>s to<br />

a cat. In each case a structuring principle makes something to be of a certain<br />

sort; <strong>and</strong> the question of how thought can relate us to things is answered by<br />

the fact that concepts <strong>and</strong> forms are isomorphic. More directly <strong>and</strong> intimately<br />

they are two ways of being of one <strong>and</strong> the same nature. This has an interesting<br />

theological implication to which I shall return.<br />

So far as epistemology is concerned the only possibility for a theory of<br />

meaning is that of an interpretative one. This brings us to the second broad<br />

camp in the philosophy of language. The effort to underst<strong>and</strong> what someone<br />

means is an effort to make sense of what they are saying, to construe it in one<br />

way or another by assigning a content to it. Practically this is something we<br />

do without much, if any, thought about guiding principles; but theoretically it<br />

is no easy task to say what the constraints on interpretation are. Donald<br />

Davidson, who follows Quine in regarding the theory of meaning as the<br />

theory of interpretative translation, has proposed various principles the common<br />

core of which is that if we are to underst<strong>and</strong> a speaker we must be able<br />

to see him or her as saying things that we might reasonably say were we in his<br />

or her circumstances. 4<br />

Interpretation of the sort in question is making human sense of human<br />

words <strong>and</strong> deeds. In doing this we cannot appeal to behavioural laws or<br />

reduce the task to the application of other causal regularities, like observers<br />

on the beach watching the motion of the waves. Instead we have to enter into<br />

the ocean of meanings <strong>and</strong> values <strong>and</strong> find our bearings there. To do so, all<br />

we have to rely on is our considered judgement as to what seems plausible,<br />

significant or compelling. If Smart is willing to allow cultural studies the<br />

status of knowledge then he will have to countenance meanings <strong>and</strong> nonscientific<br />

modes of underst<strong>and</strong>ing. But once this is conceded there is no<br />

longer any good reason (if there ever was one) not to allow emotional <strong>and</strong><br />

intuitive responses, as well as scientific enquiry <strong>and</strong> philosophical reasoning, to<br />

inform our opinions about the nature of reality. With this further broadening<br />

in mind let me recommend the following reformulation of the methodological<br />

principle: an important guide to metaphysical truth is plausibility in the light<br />

of total underst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

2 The Existence of God<br />

How does theism fare given this principle? In my essay (chapter 2) I offered<br />

arguments to the existence of God that fall under two broad patterns: teleological

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!