12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

218 J.J.C. Smart<br />

come just from the proper functioning of our faculties of sight, hearing, etc.<br />

as when we see that there is a bird on the gatepost. In his theory God has<br />

provided us with a faculty whose proper function is (after appropriate stimuli)<br />

to have an immediate perception of the truth of theism <strong>and</strong> the proper<br />

functioning of this faculty can itself be a warrant no less than sight as in the<br />

case of the bird on the gatepost. Thus Plantinga in an important sense is not<br />

a fideist. According to him we have not just faith but warrant. However,<br />

I will not attempt to summarise Plantinga’s ingenious <strong>and</strong> complex epistemology.<br />

From a Darwinian point of view we might explain the reliability of our<br />

sense organs by evolution by natural selection. Whereas Plantinga’s idea of<br />

the function of a theistic faculty requires intrusion of the supernatural that<br />

a naturalist philosopher will find implausible. It is not that Plantinga expects<br />

to convince the naturalistic philosopher of the truth of theism but he does<br />

expect to convince us that from his point of view theism is rational.<br />

I wish to remind the reader, however, that <strong>Haldane</strong> <strong>and</strong> I are metaphysical<br />

realists. If one person believes p <strong>and</strong> the other not-p, even if neither can prove<br />

one or the other proposition to the satisfaction of the other person, one or the<br />

other proposition is true. Truth must be distinguished from provability or<br />

being warrantedly assertible.<br />

The examples of Swinburne <strong>and</strong> Plantinga illustrate my view that knockdown<br />

arguments are rarely possible in philosophy, but one may hope to<br />

persuade a class of readers with similar background assumptions, <strong>and</strong> perhaps<br />

even induce a little uneasiness in some others.<br />

Prima facie it is odd to see faith as a form of knowledge. Faith occurs when<br />

people do not know. (In a religious context. Faith that your pilot won’t crash<br />

your plane is very different, because you have good empirical reasons for<br />

believing in his competence.) A scientifically plausible epistemology raises<br />

difficulties for religious faith. <strong>Common</strong> sense gives good empirical reasons for<br />

the reliability of our eyes <strong>and</strong> ears, <strong>and</strong> this is reinforced by considerations of<br />

the selective advantages in evolution of a capacity for veridical perception,<br />

whether simple or sophisticated. Perhaps there might be a scientific theory of<br />

how faith works <strong>and</strong> perhaps of how it might have survival value independently<br />

of its being veridical or otherwise.<br />

Even a pure fideist might think that his or her faith gives assurance against<br />

Humean scepticism about laws of nature. He or she might argue that since<br />

knowledge exists theism must be true. This looks like Kantian transcendental<br />

argument <strong>and</strong> so as an explanation is back to front. This is not as impossible<br />

a position as might as first appear, at least if we do not see it as an objection<br />

that different faiths conflict. Nevertheless it requires the premise that knowledge<br />

is possible. Since Hume we have been aware of the impossibility of<br />

validating scientific inductive practices. At least in science we submit our<br />

hypotheses to empirical test.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!