12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

136 J.J. <strong>Haldane</strong><br />

above to show that such a mind is simple, unique, unchanging, <strong>and</strong> so on.<br />

Yet, precisely this addition may seem to create the sort of problem that the<br />

objector envisaged. For if I wish to say that God is unchanging, this raises<br />

the prospect that he is not in time (assuming as many have done that change<br />

<strong>and</strong> time are correlative); <strong>and</strong> if I also want to claim that temporal effects are<br />

due to his agency, I then seem to have advanced a contradiction: that God’s<br />

activity is both inside <strong>and</strong> outside of time. Or it may be supposed that even to<br />

attribute thought to God is to ascribe a temporal <strong>and</strong> complex process incompatible<br />

with his eternity <strong>and</strong> impassibility.<br />

The issue of divine eternity is an intricately structured one <strong>and</strong> for present<br />

purposes I am happy to adopt the view that God is timeless in the sense<br />

(whatever exactly that is) of being ‘outside’ time. How then can he act in it?<br />

I do not think it is an option for the theist to deny divine agency in the world,<br />

not least because I have endorsed the view that the only way to reason to<br />

God’s existence is from his (or here one might better say ‘its’) effects. But the<br />

claim that God produces effects ‘in time’ is ambiguous, since the temporal<br />

reference may either be to God’s effects or to his agency. So far as mundane<br />

action is concerned both the causing <strong>and</strong> the being effected are temporal, but<br />

once again this is not something that is implied by the idea of agency as such.<br />

To hold that A caused B is only to maintain that B is due to A, <strong>and</strong> it is a<br />

further step, therefore, to claim that if B occurred at t then A must also have<br />

occurred at some time t′ (presumably prior to or simultaneous with t). Of<br />

course, someone may reply that such agency as we are familiar with, i.e. our<br />

own, is temporally situated. That, however, is beside the point. For what<br />

would have to be demonstrated is that if the effects of an action are temporal<br />

then so must be the action.<br />

A similar rejoinder is available in response to the claim that thought<br />

involves time <strong>and</strong> complexity. Human thinking takes time <strong>and</strong> makes use<br />

of ‘separate pieces’ – for example as we fashion a chain of reasoning out of<br />

initially unconnected symbols. But it is possible to assign these facts to what<br />

are plausibly contingent features of human mental processes. The defining<br />

characteristics of reasoning, as contrasted with mere psychological activity,<br />

are atemporal features, for example entailment <strong>and</strong> contradiction. Consider<br />

the following elementary modus ponens proof:<br />

If you are reading this then you must be awake<br />

You are reading this<br />

∴ You must be awake<br />

What makes this a valid piece of logic are certain abstract features <strong>and</strong> not<br />

any empirical relations between a series of marks on paper. In acknowledging<br />

this fact we see the need to distinguish between the (logical) content of a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!